Introduction: Methods and Interests | |
|
|
The Study of Argument |
|
It’s pretty clear
from our discussion of Socrates that arguments are at the heart of
philosophy. Of course the same might be said for many types of study, but
philosophy is different in at least two ways. In the first place,
philosophy has no other method of establishing its results (such as they
are) but argument. There is no experimental component, no documentary or
archival component, no observational component to philosophy. There is
nothing but argument. In the second place, the nature of argument is
itself of interest to a philosopher. The kinds of arguments that there are
and how effective they are are themselves the subjects of study (and
argument of course.) The point of
studying arguments in an abstract
way is that it allows us to know things about
particular arguments in which we
may be more immediately interested. It’s often possible, for example to
determine whether an argument is good or bad without knowing anything at
all about the actual content of the argument. Sometimes it is the
shape of the argument alone that
is important. The branch of philosophy that deals most abstractly with
argument is called logic, and though we won’t actually study it, since
it’s a bit dry and technical for an introductory course, we’ll often have
occasion to use its terminology and discoveries in the rest of the course,
so here are a few brief comments that I hope will be useful. I’m also
going to use this to show you how we talk abstractly about arguments so
you won’t be too alarmed when this sort of thing occurs in later lectures
- when we discuss things that are already hard enough to understand. To start with the
very basics: arguments are tools for persuading people of things. They
offer a number of reasons or
premises that are supposed to support a
conclusion. There are two
different big classes of arguments that are distinguished by the degree to
which the premises are supposed to support the conclusion.
Socrates is a man
All men are mortal
Therefore Socrates is mortal
Where the reasons are written above the line and the
conclusion is below it.
You can see here that
if the premises are true then the conclusion must be true. This is the
definition of a valid deductive
argument. On the other hand, any
deductive argument in which the conclusion could – somehow –
be false even when the reasons are true is an
invalid argument.
Swan number 1 is white
Swan number 2 is white
Therefore all swans are white
This is not a good inductive argument. In a good one
if the premises are true then they make the conclusion probably true.
This is the definition of a strong
inductive argument. On the other hand, an inductive argument
like the example, in which, even if the premises were true they wouldn’t
make the conclusion
probably true, is a
weak argument.
| |
Logical
matters | |
So let’s now have a slightly closer look at the argument that Socrates offered to Euthyphro. As we’ve interpreted it, it went something like this. 1.
Socrates gets from
Euthyphro a definition of
‘piety:’ Piety is what the gods love
and impiety is what the gods hate. 2.
Socrates then derives
certain consequences of this
definition. Since we
know that the gods have disagreements And we
know that the only fundamental causes of disagreement are differences over
the matter of right and wrong. It
follows that the gods differ over
right and wrong Then,
since we know that everyone loves
what is right and hates what is wrong It
follows that the gods love and
hate different things – or, which is the same thing, the same things are
loved and hated by different gods And we
have assumed that piety is what
the gods love and impiety is what the gods hate. And
so the same things are both pious
and impious 3.
Finally deriving the conclusion
that: Piety cannot be just what the gods love
and impiety what they hate. It’s this last step that I want to talk about.
It’s a variety of a very basic deductive argument called (in Latin) modus tollens. A modus tollens argument is an
argument of a very particular form. It basically goes
If A then B
Not B
Therefore not A Where A and B stand for sentences or
‘propositions.’ It’s easy to see what’s going on here if I give a couple
of simple examples: Let’s replace A by ‘It has been raining’ and B by
‘The grass is wet’ in the argument form above. Then we get this
argument:
If it has been raining then the grass is wet
The grass is not wet
Therefore it has not been raining Which you can see is a valid argument because if the reasons are true (that’s the two statements above the line) then the conclusion (below the line) must be true. It is impossible for the reasons to be true and the conclusion false. If we replace A by, say, ‘Socrates is a man’, and
B by ‘Socrates is mortal’, then we get the argument
If Socrates is a man then Socrates is mortal
Socrates is not mortal
Therefore Socrates is not a man Which is also a valid argument – despite the fact that the
2nd reason in that argument was actually false, because
Socrates turned out to be quite mortal. His mortality was proved shortly
after the trial that he was on his way to when he met Euthyphro. But it
doesn’t matter that one of the reasons is false, because to be valid it is
only necessary that if the
reasons were true then the
conclusion would be true. And as you can see, if those reasons were true
then the conclusion would be too. If all the reasons are true, and the
argument is valid then the conclusion will be true too. Just as a matter
of interest, a valid argument with true reasons is called a sound
argument. Anyway, the important point to note is that, as
you’ve probably already realised, any argument which has the modus tollens form will be valid,
which is why we call it a valid
form. Now, this particular argument winds up with
Socrates and Euthyphro deriving a contradiction, which everyone agrees
can’t be a true statement: it’s never true that the sun is shining and at the very same time and place
the sun is not shining, or that the grass is green and at the very same
time the grass is not green, or (and this is the important point) that
something is loved by the gods and at the very same time not loved by the gods. So:
If piety is what is loved by the gods then the same things are
pious and not pious
The same things are not
at the very same time pious and not pious
Therefore piety is not what is loved by the
gods This is obviously modus tollens where A = ‘piety is
what is loved by the gods’ and B is ‘the same things are pious and not
pious.’[1]
Because it is modus tollens, it
is valid – as I’ve just demonstrated. This means that if the reasons are
true then the conclusion is true. We’ve already seen that the
2nd reason is true; but what about the first one? What about
the claim that ‘If piety is what is loved by the gods then the same things
are pious and not pious.’ Well, this is a statement that summarises the
result of the first two steps of Socrates’s argument. Remember, they
assumed the truth of Euthyphro’s claim that ‘piety is what is loved by the
gods’ and derived from it by simple steps that they both agreed on that
‘the same things are pious and not pious.’ The conditional statement just
summarises that process. So we have to assume that it is true also. And
finally, if the argument is valid (modus tollens) and the reasons are
true (so the argument is sound) then, ta dah!, the conclusion is true and
‘piety is not what is loved by the gods.’ [1] This particular style of argument is one you may have heard of: it is called reductio ad absurdum, meaning ‘reducing to an absurdity.’ | |
Philosophy and
science | |
The reason that I particularly wanted to introduce
you to this kind of argument is because it closely resembles the
methodology of a form of enquiry for which you probably already have some
degree of respect. I’m talking about the methodology of Science – which we
all believe has the ability to tell us true (or, at least, useful things
about the world. In a scientific enquiry, there is some observed
phenomenon for which an explanation is sought: it may be that we are
wondering why a compass needle points towards the North, or why a stick
appears to bend as it goes into the water, or why water boils when it is
heated. How is it that scientists (ideal scientists, that is) go about
answering such a question? The best known account of the scientific method
is one that goes by the name of the hypothetico-deductive procedure.
It can be seen as a process consisting of the following four
steps. 1.
Form
a hypothesis (e.g., by generalising or by an educated guess) of some
possible explanation for the phenomenon 2.
Derive
testable consequences from the hypothesis. 3.
Test
for these consequences. 4.
Confirm
or disconfirm the hypothesis. If
the derived consequences of the hypothesis are observed, then the
hypothesis is said to be confirmed. If they are not observed, the
hypothesis is said to be disconfirmed or falsified. The hypothesis is
either tentatively accepted if it is confirmed by the test, or rejected or
amended if ‘disconfirmed’ by the test. Let’s see how this is supposed to work by
considering the actual historical case of coming up with an explanation
for why we sometimes see the same collections of fossilized flora and
fauna on opposite sides of oceans. When scientists (geographers) became aware of this
phenomenon, they probably first thought that it was a simple matter of
animals swimming across the water, but it quickly became clear that the
sorts of animals whose fossils were being found wouldn’t have been able to
swim that far because the gaps were too wide. So how could this common
ecology have arisen? The first serious hypothesis was that the separate
areas had been connected in the past by extensive land bridges crossing
the Atlantic or the Indian oceans. Plants and animals could have moved
across these bridges in the past, and become isolated from each other
after the bridges were worn away over time. In support of this theory
there was the observation that there were known land bridges which had
connected Siberia to Alaska and Britain to Europe and that had been
submerged by rising sea levels after the end of the last ice age only a
few tens of thousands of years ago. But there was a problem: if there had been such
enormous bridges as proposed, then there ought to still be some traces of
them, but there were none. Because of this (and other reasons) they could
not really be happy with the land bridge idea. In the mid-twentieth
century, therefore, they began to revive an old hypothesis that the
continents had all been joined together at some time far in the past and
had gradually drifted apart. According to this story the fossils were the
remains of inhabitants of a single habitat that had subsequently been
divided. There were of course those who doubted this
theory. Continents, after all, are made of rock and it’s hard to imagine
that they move around much. Indeed, said the critics, if this theory is
true then you’d have to assume that the continents were still moving. So, are they? Well,
with new accurate measuring equipment it was possible to test this
hypothesis too, and it was found that they were moving. As time went on, more
and more evidence was found to support the theory of continental drift –
what they now call Plate
Tectonics – until it is now quite widely
accepted. The similarity of the hypothetico-deductive method
to the Socratic method of elenchus should be clear. The moral of the
story, however, is that we can’t take the method itself, or the use of mere
logic, to be the distinctive feature of philosophical enquiry. Indeed,
philosophers would like to see themselves as engaged in just the same
serious enquiry into the truth of things as are scientists. More than
that, they consider that science is secondary to philosophy in this
pursuit. This is partly because philosophy has been done for much longer
than science, but also because science tends to follow philosophy in the
treatment of particular topics. For example, physics, astronomy,
cosmology, chemistry, biology, mathematics, economics, psychology,
cognitive science, and many others all used to be considered part of philosophy, or
arose from philosophical reflections. The question that
naturally arises, then, is: what makes us call the modern treatment
science and the ancient treatment philosophy? Or, what was philosophy
doing in those areas that science does not do? The fundamental answer is that when some field of study appeals to the evidence of the natural world to answer the questions it asks then we are doing something like science, but when the answer is not thought to be discoverable by looking at the natural world then we must be doing something more like philosophy. At the early stages of those studies that I’ve named, the desirability – or even the possibility – of looking to the world for evidence to support answers was not always clear; but more than that, it takes some time and thought to sort out which parts of a field of study really are appropriate subjects of empirical research, and which parts are not. This process of definition is itself something that can only be done by philosophical methods. In the matter of ethics, for example, it is a real step forward to become aware of the distinction between what people actually do (which may be studied in the sciences of social psychology, anthropology, cultural history, ethology, etc.) and what they ought to do (which may be studied by moral philosophers) In the matter of cosmology, it is a step forward to become aware of the distinction between how and where the universe began (which may be studied by astronomers and cosmologists and physicists) and why the universe exists rather than not existing – for which no scientific answer can be had. In the study of the human mind, as we shall see, the questions of how memory works and how we sense things and how we process information are open to scientific scrutiny by psychologists and cognitive scientists, but the question of whether a machine can think like a human is not one that any science can answer (yet?)
| |
Philosophy and
concepts | |
|
So what role does
philosophy play in the pursuit of truth – even truths about the world – if
it is not apparently truth that can be tested against the world? The
standard answer to such a question is that philosophy aims to clarify the
concepts that we are using to understand the world. Many people claim that
we make the transition from doing philosophy in some area of enquiry to
doing science in that area when philosophy has clarified or corrected the
concepts involved to such a degree that they correspond to the way that
the world actually is and we can then ask questions that the world can
answer. There’s a particularly
clear example of this from the early days of science & philosophy.
Some of the most heated early disputes of the ancient Greek physicists
were over the nature or even the possibility of change or motion. The
Greeks could see as well as we can see that the world is full of change,
but because of certain apparently sound arguments it sometimes seemed that
change could not really be possible, and that our evidence of change must
therefore be illusory. Consider, they would say, how it is possible for a
ball to move. A ball cannot move to the right unless everything that was
to the right of the ball is moved to make room for it. And where would all
that stuff go? It would have to go into places vacated by other stuff. And
then where would that stuff go.
The problem is that in a universe that is full of stuff, there is no way
to move stuff around. It would be like trying to move bricks around in an
unbroken wall. You might think that
the obvious solution to this would be to suppose (as we do today) that the
world isn’t just a block of stuff but has empty spaces which things can
move into without first having to displace other stuff. But this solution
wasn’t immediately apparent to the Greeks, because they did not properly
distinguish the concepts of matter and space. We now think of matter as occupying space, but the Greeks
began by thinking of matter as constituting space. And why
wouldn’t they? What experience could they have had of space without matter
filling it? And if matter is
space, then it can make no sense to think of something moving into
some space where there is no matter. (A space where there is no matter is
no space at all!) Until those two concepts – and the related concept of
the ‘void’ or ‘nothingness’ – had been properly distinguished, this
paradox of the impossibility of change in an obviously change-filled world
just could not be solved. And in case you’re
thinking that this sort of nonsense is far in our past, and there’s no
need to keep up the philosophical work of concept clarification in a field
as well developed as Physics, I would direct your attention to two much
more recent difficulties. When Newton proposed that there was a force of
Gravity acting between all the masses in the universe, his idea was
ridiculed as requiring ‘spooky action at a distance.’ It had been clear
since ancient times that the only way that one thing could cause a change
in another thing was by coming into contact with it: for there are simply
no other forces but mechanical forces – that’s just what forces are! But
the moon doesn’t come into contact with the Earth, nor the Earth with the
Sun, so it’s clearly impossible that any influences can be exerted amongst
those bodies. My last example is
completely contemporary. Beginning in the 20th C, physicists
studying the behavior of light found that they had to accept that in some
situations it behaved as if it were constituted of particles and in other
situations it behaved as if it were simply waves in some medium. And
eventually, it was accepted that all matter showed the same tendency
towards a wave-particle duality. There is more to this dualism than a mere
ambiguity about what matter is, for it sometimes seems that matter looks
at the circumstances and then decides how to behave, which of course is
absurd. And without an example you won’t really grasp how weird matter is
– so take the time sometime to look at the double slit
experiment. The really impressive thing is that despite the
fact that we have had to pragmatically accept this wave-particle dualism
of matter for over a hundred years now, we are still in the process of
trying to make conceptual sense of it. Well, that’s one good
reason for being interested in conceptual clarification – and thus in
doing philosophy right; but there’s a more basic reason to value it, and
it has to do with our nature as human beings. What chiefly characterizes
us as humans, we often think, is our status as thinking, rational animals.
The most striking evidence for this characterization is the fact that we,
more than any other thing in the universe, can be properly described as intentional agents – which is a
fancy way of saying that our actions are best predicted or
explained by assuming that we use reason to decide how to achieve
our desires given the things
that we believe. For example,
when we feel that we need to eat – that is we have a desire for food – we
reason from the fact that there is food at Bond Café, and we have money to
buy food at the café, and it is open now, but we are not allowed to eat in
class, but we can eat later – all of which are beliefs that we have – we
decide that we will walk there later to buy food. Finally, when class is
finished we stand up and walk out the door and proceed in the direction of
Bond Café – which is the action that we take to satisfy our desire for
food. Obviously, the most
important parts of this Belief-Desire-Action process are internal, and
involve the use of representations of the world. I mean that it’s probably
not possible to think about going to the shops, or buying food there with
money, or satisfying your hunger, etc. without having some concepts of
those things. And the reason that this process works well for us must have
something to do with the fact that the concepts correspond in some
systematic way with the facts of the world. To take an extreme case, if
our idea of food included things like nails and detergent, then we’d be as
likely to go to Bunning’s as to Bond Café, and we’d fail to satisfy our
hunger. So it’s pretty important to make sure that our concepts of things
match up to what’s really going on in the world. Obviously,
again, we’re well past the point where we need to worry about what our
concept of ‘food’ is to include, but remember that we started all this
talk by looking at a particular problem that Socrates had with the concept
of ‘piety’, which might seem to us still to be something a bit up in the
air. Or, if you think that piety is simply a badly formed concept not
referring to anything Real, then we could consider some later examples. In
recent times, for example, we’ve had significant political problems which
revolved around divergent understandings of concepts such as ‘human’ (in
the abortion debate or the Terry Schiavo case) or with ‘privacy’, or with
‘rights’, or with ‘marriage’, or etc. As you can see from these topics,
Philosophy still has a lot of work to do.
|