The Meaning of Life | |
|
|
Introduction |
|
|
The question of the Meaning of Life is one of those questions that the layman thinks should be at the very heart of the philosophical enterprise, and yet it is not something that has been of much interest to serious philosophers in the past, whether professional or amateur. There have, of course, been some attempts over the course of the millennia, but nothing approaching the prolonged and systematic efforts directed at questions of such perennial interest as ‘What is Good?’, ‘What is Truth?’, ‘What can we Know?’, ‘Is there a God?’, or ‘What is Beauty?’ And even amongst the topics of recent interest it has not really featured as the centre of its own field of study as has mind, or language. Nevertheless, it has been taken up more recently – but with what success it remains to be seen.
|
What is the Question? |
|
|
There’s an amusing scene in
Douglas Adams’ Hitchhikers’
Guide to the Galaxy[1]
where a vast supercomputer built by a race of hyper-intelligent
pan-dimensional beings is asked to answer the ultimate question of
‘Life, the Universe, and Everything.’ After 7½ million years Deep
Thought gives the answer “42.” Naturally, this is a disappointment,
and Deep Thought is asked to explain itself: “I
think the problem, to be quite honest with you, is that you’ve never
actually known what the question is.” ”But it was the Great
Question! The Ultimate Question of Life, the Universe and Everything!”
howled Loonquawl. ”Yes,” said Deep Thought
with the air of one who suffers fools gladly,” but what actually is
it?” A slow stupefied silence crept
over the men as they stared at the computer and then at each other. ”Well, you know, it’s just
Everything . . . Everything . . . ” offered Phouchg weakly. ”Exactly!” said Deep
Thought. ”So once you do know what the question actually is, you’ll
know what the answer means.” We’re not quite in that
position, since we do have a perfectly grammatically correct question to
answer: to whit, “What is the Meaning of Life?” On the other hand our
position is very similar because the meaning of the question itself
isn’t exactly clear. And we can’t know what sort of thing would even
count as an answer to this question until we get that clear – although
we are pretty sure that “42” isn’t the answer. So, how should we understand the
question? Well, notwithstanding what I have just
said, I don’t think that we can work it out by investigating the
semantics of the terms involved. In fact the way to get at what people
mean by this question is exactly
to look at the sorts of answers that have been proposed. But don’t
worry; this isn’t quite as absurd as it appears. (We’ll get to
absurdity later, I assure you.) Think of it this way: people have felt the
need for a solution to some vaguely felt problem – not yet well defined
in their own minds. They have proposed solutions or responses that seem to
them to be properly directed at this vaguely felt problem, and they have
at the same time tried to express the problem with which they are
concerned. From inspection of the answers, we can determine whether the
question is well-framed. If not, then we modify the question so that the
answer makes more sense. From inspection of the question, we can determine
whether there is a coherent problem being addressed. If not, then we can
either dismiss the whole pursuit, or modify the question to make it more
coherent. (This is something like an approach we call ‘reflective
equilibrium,’ where we adjust related but incoherent beliefs and
intuitions piecemeal until they are
coherent.) Luckily, we can start with better answers than “42,” and
better questions than “What do you get if you multiply six by nine.” It doesn’t always work, of
course. It might be that there are, in fact, several different questions
being asked and we would then need to distinguish them. Some people think
that this is exactly what’s going on, and that no answer is going to be
entirely satisfactory because if it perfectly answers one of the
questions, it will leave others unanswered. In any case, I’m not going to
pursue that reflective process here – because life is short and time is
brief – instead, I’m just going to mention a couple of the possible
interpretations of the question that have been thought to be good. Thus: 1.
What
is the significance of life – or of one’s life (or what should it be.) 2.
What
is the purpose of life – or of one’s life (or what should it be.) [1]
Adams, D. (1979) Hitchhikers’
Guide to the Galaxy,
p. 121. |
A Question of Significance? |
|
|
So let’s consider this
first possible interpretation. And again we notice that although this
seems more precise than the original form, yet there are still several
ways that this can be understood. We’ll just look at two.
Is
Man’s Life Significant? In the first place, they might
be wondering what is the place of Mankind in the Universe. Are we
important and how? And to whom? It would be nice to think that humans are
objectively pretty special, but is that just a conceit? We used to think
that we were the special creation of God – the purpose of the whole
creation was tied up in our salvation. Our home, the Earth, was the centre
of the Universe and we were the most important thing on it. But the story
of our self-image since the beginning of the Modern era has been one of
continued diminution. We have discovered that the Earth isn’t the centre
of the universe, but goes around the Sun. And the Sun isn’t the centre
either, it’s a perfectly unremarkable main sequence, yellow dwarf,
middle-aged star 25,000 light years from the centre of a typical spiral
galaxy in a universe so vast that it is literally beyond our
comprehension. We’ve also discovered that our recorded history of 5000
years is about a tenth of the time that humans have existed, and only 1
millionth of the age of the Earth, and even less than that of the
Universe. We’ve also found that Man was not distinguished by a special
creation from all the other creatures of the Earth, but arose through the
processes of evolution from some common, vanished, barely living
non-cellular organism. We are an accident that has happened in no special
time or place; tiny, momentary, and insignificant. Even our mighty brains
are the development of smaller brains and eventually of the tiniest spinal
bulges. The software which ran on them continues to run in us, and
although Freud’s psychology is no longer credible, his original insight
that our minds are much darker than we had imagined remains valid. We are
closer to the beasts than to the angels that we have imagined. On the other hand of course, the
Earth is the only place in all this vast universe that we know has life on
it. And we are by a long, long margin the smartest things that have ever
lived on the Earth. And we are not only smart but self-aware and
conscious, and we can think about ourselves, and our awareness, and we can
recognise Good and Evil, and True and False, and Beautiful and Ugly, and
we can speculate on possibilities and necessities, in ways that no other
creatures are able to do. And we can tell each other about all these
things using language which is unknown outside humans. This means that we
have value in a way that all the rest of creation does not. Just consider:
a rock has no value in itself, but only as it is valued by a person or
some other thinking, valuing creature. (Remember, we talked about this
when we looked at Kant’s defence of the Does
Life Signify Anything? But perhaps the ‘meaning’ in
the original question is more like the meaning in the question: “What is
the meaning of the play ‘King Lear’?” In this case we now have a
question of interpretation. We are asking “What does this play
signify?” But by ‘signify’ now, we want to know how this play should
be understood in some deeper sense. How should it make us feel and how
should it affect our view of the world when we hear it conclude? I think
this gets us closer to the idea behind the question, but now it looks as
if there’s supposed to be some over-riding theme or intention in the
story of our life that can be interpreted at its end – and most people
will seriously doubt whether there is any such thing, because they’re
too aware of the many contingencies (accidents and luck) that went into
the forming of their life story. Did you pass that exam to become a pilot
or did you get drunk the night before and fail? Did you speak to the girl
at the shop who would have been your wife or was she distracted by a car
going past and turned away from? So many trivial causes with such huge
effects, this surely can’t be how a meaningful story is written. And if we do think that this is
the only way to give a life a meaning, and that no life can have such a
theme or plan, then we may conclude that no life has
any such meaning. Thus it follows that life is meaningless, and we
might as well stop trying. Then we might agree with the words of
Shakespeare’s Macbeth[1]
when he tells us that Life's
but a walking shadow, a poor player Thus, nihilism. What exactly is the point of going on living a life which has no meaning? Why go on living? But we’ll get back to Nihilism; we have other options to explore before that. [1]
Macbeth,
Act 5, Scene 5
|
A Question of Purpose? |
|
|
So now let’s consider
the question of purpose. Again, we find that the question is possibly more
precise – at least it seems to direct us toward certain answers while
ruling out some others – and yet there are still several ways of taking
it. What
Makes a Life Valuable? One way of taking it is to ask
what things there are that make a life have or gain value, so the question
of meaning becomes the question of purpose becomes the question of “What
Makes a Life Valuable?” And this seems naturally enough to point to the
problem of determining what system of values is appropriate to us. Now, you might think that this
is actually quite an easy question to answer, and that the answer would be
the sort of thing that we might have treated in the section on Ethics.
What are we to do? Why, the Good, of course; and the only difficulty –
which we will claim has proved great but does not seem to be a
priori insurmountable – is to decide what the Good is. At the very
least, in this question we think we have something that we can get our
teeth into. But let me remind you of some of the difficulties that are
involved in this question (and note that they’ve been mentioned in
passing earlier.) First, consider the Utilitarian definition of Good as
being that which produces the greatest good for the greatest number. An
essay question on this topic asks you to compare what you’d be required
to do if you really believed this with what you’re likely to value doing
more highly. Is this a fault in you or in the ethical theory? Second,
remember the visitor to the hospital who goes only out of Duty and never
out of spontaneous desire to see their sick mother. They value only doing
the right thing, and we say, don’t we that that is not enough. Something
of value is omitted from such a life. Finally, you might be some kind of
Hedonist, possibly a utilitarian again, who thinks that the ultimate moral
value is pleasure – or perhaps you even believe that the only thing
worth pursuing is pleasure – but that doesn’t mean that you’d agree
that a life spent in a happiness machine could be counted as a well-spent
life. There’s some value determinative of a well-spent life which
isn’t to be found by maximising that moral quality. And this is
perfectly typical of moral theories. So it looks as if something is
missing from such theories that we would require in the sort of theory
that we’d take to be an answer to the question of meaning/purpose/value. The point of all this is just
that if we are going to find a value for Life then we’re going to have
to look elsewhere than in the places that we’ve already looked for
value. And if we locate a candidate it will have to be able to pass the
sorts of tests that the ‘moral’ values just failed. Perhaps you can
think of some candidates, but let’s now move on to another approach. Does
Life Have Some End at which it Aims? Another way of taking the
purpose question is to ask whether there is some overall goal at which
Life aims or at which any individual life aims (or, in either case, should aim.) Thus the question as we’ll understand it is “What
is the Goal of Life?” The answers to this question are usually divided
(neatly, but somewhat naively) into those goals that come from within
ourselves, and those that come from without. We’ll start with the
latter. i.
God’s
Purpose Determines Our Purpose The obvious external source of
purposes is God. But that is not the only source: Marxists, for example,
saw themselves as agents for the impersonal forces of History itself. But
let’s deal with the more plausible alternative. (Note that in what
follows I’m going to assume that it’s the Christian God that is at
issue here. Other types of theism would presumably provide other types of
meaningfulness.) The
Christian reasoning is fairly straightforward. God is the benevolent
creator of the world. God rules the world, and does so according to
rational principles. God has a rational plan for the world, which is to
say, a plan to achieve some aims by means of the created world. (We know
that God has plans with respect to the world because we know that God is
rational and wouldn’t do anything without a reason.) ‘God
… so orders all events within the universe that the end for which it was
created may be realized.’[1]
As parts of this creation, our purposes are subordinate to the purposes of
God. It only remains for us to discover how our purposes ought to be so
aligned, and what our subordinate purposes ought to be. The
best way to do this would be to determine what God’s purpose is and to
adopt rhose subordinate purposes that reason would declare to be necessary
to its achievement. Unfortunately,
God is never quite explicit about what His purpose is, and we are reduced
to assuming that behaving in the way that God wants us to behave, or
adopting the values that God wants us to have are sufficient to the
purpose. So how do we determine those? Well, in the first place, God’s plan,
that ‘so orders events,’ Aquinas identifies with “Eternal Law,”
part of which is the “Natural Law” which gives us our moral guidance.
And we are able to determine through reason, says Aquinas, what the
Natural Law commands. Good. So that tells us how we are to behave. In the
second place, the Christian tradition recognises a simple guide to the sort of things
that make life worth living. We are supposed to feel love for our
neighbours. A special sort of love that is denoted agaph in
the tradition and which also denotes the type of love that God feels for
us. Because we are loved by God, and because it is incumbent upon us to
love what God loves, it follows that we should love one another, and so: You have heard that it was said, 'Love (agape) your neighbor and
hate your enemy.' But I tell you: Love your enemies and pray for those who
persecute you, that you may be sons of your Father in heaven. He causes
his sun to rise on the evil and the good, and sends rain on the righteous
and the unrighteous.[2]
If you love those who love you, what reward will you get?[3] Love,
then, of this special sort is the value that we derive from the assumption
of God. And we have a perfectly comprehensible motivator for our actions.
Especially those which satisfy the little rubric
Do unto others as you would have others do unto you. Of
course, there are a few difficulties with all of this – even ignoring
the arguments that led to this point. The first of these is a version of
the Euthyphro problem that you might remember from earlier. If the
necessary and sufficient condition for the goals we pursue being worth
pursuing is that God says to pursue them, then we’d have to accept that
if God said that we should stand on our heads, that would be our goal in
life. This would be unacceptable, so we must have some criteria
independent of God. If that’s the case, then we really haven’t solved
the problem of the source of our goals. Another
problem might be that you doubt that there is a God anyway, and so
there’s no getting a purpose by subordinating yourself to God’s
purposes. But thinking of a world in which there is no God, would it seem
reasonable to suppose that that lack by itself made our lives meaningless,
whereas they would have had meaning otherwise. And looking at the people
you admire: would you think it likely that what they were doing was
meaningless if there’s no God, but meaningful otherwise? None of this
seems reasonable to me. ii.
We
Determine Our Own Purposes a.
Our
Life as Lived Determines Our Purpose Let’s
put that aside then and consider the idea that our purposes have an internal source. Think of the lives of some people that we might
admire: people such as Mother Theresa or Jonas Salk or Norman Borlaug or
Shakespeare or Bach or Mahatma Gandhi or Thomas Jefferson or Winston
Churchill, or others who’ve made a mark on the world. How much better
the world is because they were in it! Some of these people may have
adopted their forms of life because of some sort of deep thought about the
sorts of things that they valued and how to advance their interests. Most
probably did not, but simply got on with the business of living and found
to their surprise that there were values that were worth their allegiance.
It may
be that this is the most common way of discovering a meaning in life. We
experience life as meaningful if we live it in pursuit of values that have
the capacity to inspire us and to claim our attachment to them. And those
values need not be discovered through philosophical thought – indeed,
they might not be able to withstand even slight philosophical scrutiny as
final values – but can be discovered in the course of simply living
one’s life. These are the sorts of values that are created for one who
accidentally becomes responsible for a child and learns to value that
child’s welfare, or who discovers injustice in their place of work and
becomes a union organiser, and so on. If this is really the source of the
values that motivate us then the appropriate advice for us all is the
phrase seen on Australian TV:
Life, be in it. b.
We Can Simply Declare a Meaning and Live Accordingly That,
however, is a pretty unphilosophical way to go about things. It leaves one
vulnerable to the charge that one is not living a fully considered life;
and, of course, it means that the meaning one has found in life is
vulnerable to the criticisms of the cynic and the nihilist. A more
robust, and I think more respectable philosophy of life can be found in an
alternative option: that we choose what our life is to mean. This is the
sort of thing that has in recent times been most often associated with the
philosophical position of Existentialism, very popular during the 50s in It’s an open question how satisfactory any of this is, however, since we might well choose to pursue goals that are not, according to my intuitions, the sorts of things that would give life meaning. We might for example, think that watching TV all day and all night was worth doing, or collecting stamps, or jumping on one foot. Once again, it looks as if we have intuitions of what could be valuable that don’t allow the free choice of ends that this position would defend. But are our intuitions grounded in anything substantial/objective/real? It seems that we haven’t actually gotten very far in this enquiry.
[1] Catholic Encyclopaedia, s.v. ‘Divine Providence’ (http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/12510a.htm ) [2]
The rain it raineth on the just
and on the unjust feller.
But mostly on the just because
The unjust hath the just’s umbrella. [3]
Matt.
5:43-46
|
Nihlism? |
|
|
The apparent failure of
these attempts to find a meaning for Life has led some to adopt the
position called Nihilism: that is, to deny that there is a meaning. This
fits in nicely with the rest of our sceptical philosophizing. What can we
know? Nothing. What is good? Don’t know – so possibly nothing. Is
there a self? Probably not. How does the mind come from matter? Don’t
know – it doesn’t look like it can. Is there such a thing as a Mind?
Maybe not. And so on. It is also an old temptation, which we can see in Ecclesiastes
(1:2), for example, Vanity of vanities, saith the Preacher, vanity of
vanities; all is vanity, which probably dates to the 3rd
century BC; and also in the words of some of the Classical philosophers.
It was dormant in the time of the Christian dominance of learning, but
came roaring back with Nietzsche in modern times. Absurdity But if we adopt the nihilist
point of view, we then have an apparent incoherence or paradox or
something unwelcome, because if Life is Meaningless or without
Significance, or it has no Purpose, then there is nothing to do with your
life but just to keep living it while accepting that nothing you do has
any Meaning/Significance/Purpose. But the thing about going on living is
that you can’t just resign
yourself to it and cease to engage with life. In order to carry on living
you really have to make decisions about the things that you are required
to do from year to year, day to day, and moment to moment. You need to put
out the rubbish on Tuesday mornings, you need to go to work and try to
perform up to the appropriate standard, you may even need to put on a
happy face and wish people a nice day if you’re in the service industry.
And all of this while you are aware of the crushing burden of the futility
of life. Thomas Nagel[1],
I think, makes a special note of the obvious mismatch between the
consciously considered worth of our actions and lives, and the degree to
which our lives must be dominated by these ‘pointless’ actions. This
mismatch, he says, accounts for the persistent feeling amongst some of our
sensitive souls that life is absurd. That feeling of absurdity would be
greatest for nihilists, of course, but it is a likely feature of anyone
who thinks that life is basically trivial. In the Myth of Sisyphus Camus referred to the old Greek myth in which
Sisyphus was condemned by the gods to roll a boulder up a hill, and when
it rolled back down, to start again, and to continue this forever. This
never ending, unavoidable, ultimately futile task Camus claimed was a
model for our own lives. What, then, is to be done? We may, of course,
fall into despair and commit suicide; but this, Camus says, is simple
cowardice. We may accept a supernatural solution to the problem and take
the meaning of our life from some supposed transcendental source; but this
is merely a suicide of the rational mind, says Camus, and no more
respectful of our humanity than the previous option. Finally, we may
accept the absurdity of life and even embrace it. We accept the truth of
the situation we are in and we face it. This makes us heroic. Which I
guess is worthwhile.
|