Aristotle on Knowledge |
|
|
|
Recommended Reading Barnes, J. (1982) Aristotle
London: OUP Ackrill, J. L. (1981) Aristotle
the Philosopher London: OUP Text of Aristotle
http://classics.mit.edu/Browse/index.html
Mure,
G. R. G. Posterior Analytics Hardie,
R. P. Hardie, R. K. Gaye
Physics. Ross,
W. D. Metaphysics.
Aristotle 384–322
BC. Student of Plato, Teacher of Alexander. Founded Lyceum.
|
|
Introduction |
|
We saw previously that Plato’s theory of knowledge depended upon the
existence of a realm of so-called ‘Forms’ which are the enduringly
real ‘ideals’ of the things that exist in the mundane realm. These
Forms can be thought of as the referents of universal or general terms,
and they are required in order to explain how we can recognise that some
thing falls under a general term. When we say that some observed thing is
a dog, for example, we are recognising that the Form of Dog is somehow
inherent in that thing, or that the thing participates in the Form of Dog.
Because real knowledge is properly only of ideals, and because the world
that we see about us every day is only a poor projection from these Forms
and not at all to be trusted to tell us about how things really are,
Plato’s stance can be described as idealistic. For him, real knowledge
comes from pure contemplation on abstract things, and the evidence of the
senses can play very little role in the pursuit of knowledge. Aristotle’s attitude was quite different. He represents the class of
philosophers that we might call ‘Realists’, and he puts much more
trust in the evidence of the senses. It is from the interpretation of the
information to be gained from looking at the world that Truth can be
found.
|
|
Aristotle’s Rejection of the Forms |
|
In particular Aristotle was quite dismissive of the whole idea of
independently existing Forms. He had several arguments against them, of
which the most famous was the so-called ‘Third Man’ argument. Oddly
enough, we don’t actually have
Aristotle’s argument, but it was apparently[1]
a modification of one that Plato himself had put forward in his Parmenides
at 132a-b. There Plato says: PARMENIDES:
I imagine that the way in which you are led to assume one Form of each
kind is as follows: -You see a number of large objects, and when you look
at them there seems to you to be one and the same Form (or nature) in them
all; hence you conceive of Largeness as one thing.
The Third Man version of this would be the claim that we can recognise a
particular man as a man (let’s call him Bob) because he participates in
the Form of Man, which we are able to recognise. But we can only recognise
the Form of Man as the Form of
that particular because it and Bob participate in another Form – call it
the Third Man – which we recognise. And we only recognise the Third Man
as the Form in which Man, and Bob participate because we recognise a
Fourth Man. And we only recognise … Well, you get the idea. The
epistemological upshot of all this is that if our ability to recognise men
depends upon our becoming acquainted with the necessary Forms, then no
such knowledge is possible, for there are an infinite number of Forms with
which it is first necessary to become acquainted. And since, as Aristotle
would insist, we really do have knowledge of things like Bob being a man,
this means that the Forms are not necessary for knowledge; and so one of
the justifications for proposing them as independently existing things in
the first place is removed. The other problem with the Platonic Forms was that they didn’t seem
able to explain change. If something is increasing from small to large,
let’s say, then at one point in time it is a copy participating in the
Form of the Small and at another point it is participating in the Form of
the Large. But Plato gives us no idea of how to think of this change of
‘participations.’ The metaphor just doesn’t help.
[1] Aristotle’s book On Ideas where these arguments were elaborated is lost; our knowledge of them is largely from a commentary on his Metaphysics by Alexander of Aphrodisias written in the 2nd-3rd C. BC and including fragments of the peri idewn.
|
|
Aristotle’s Metaphysics |
|
Aristotle
does have a role for Forms, but not as independently existing things. For
Aristotle the Forms are patterns which make Matter into the things that we
find in the ‘real world.’ Matter and Form together constitute
Substance, and Substance is that to which we can apply all the useful and
informative sorts of predicates (names of properties,) which Aristotle
lists as the Categories[1].
A man, for example, is matter arranged in the pattern that is
characteristic of a man. The same matter differently arranged might have
been a duck or a dog or a daisy or a dish. All of those things are
substances: and of all of those things one can enquire about their
properties. Take the substance Socrates, for example. We can ask about the
categories of quantity (is he short?), quality (is he ugly?), relation (is
he younger or older than me?), location (is he at the market?), time (when
was he there?), position (was he standing?), habit (was he wearing
sandals?), action (was he buying something?), or passion (who was talking
to him?). This
way of looking at things meant that Aristotle was at least able to talk
about changes. When something is changing the change can be understood in
a couple of different ways: either the substance of Socrates was taking on
different properties, so that formerly standing he is now sitting, or
formerly happy he is now sad; or the matter that was the substrate of
Socrates is taking on a new pattern, so that formerly a child he is now a
man, or formerly alive he is now dead, and so on.[2]
To
go along with this view of change, Aristotle also had a view of the causes (aitia/aitia)
of change. In Physics II.3 he
says: In
one sense, then, (1) that out of which a thing comes to be and which
persists, is called 'cause', e.g. the bronze of the statue, the silver of
the bowl, and the genera of which the bronze and the silver are species.
[This is now referred to as the Material Cause]
[1] Aristotle is not consistent with his metaphysics any more than Plato is with his. Sometimes matter is said to be the primary substance, and sometimes (Met. 1041) the Form is, and sometimes (Cat. 2a11-14) the compound of the two in normal everyday objects is. For us, none of this really matters. [2] On the other hand, the permanence of Socrates from moment to moment, or the permanence of the ship of Theseus, is to be explained by supposing that the Form remains unmodified and changing matter is informed by it.
|
|
Explanations and Scientific Knowledge |
|
But
perhaps you’re not entirely convinced that all the things that Aristotle
is calling causes are really the sorts of things that you’re used to
calling causes. You are right to be cautious, because what Aristotle seems
to mean by a cause is more like what we would call an explanation. And
more than this, Aristotle also has a very definite idea of what an
explanation should look like. For Aristotle an explanation is an answer to
a question of the form ‘why is S a P?’ where S is the subject of the
enquiry and P is a property we see belongs to that subject; for example,
‘why is this statue brown (a brown thing?)’, ‘why is the moon
eclipsed (an eclipsed thing?)’, ‘why is the child ugly?’, ‘why go
walking?’, and so on. So
what sort of thing will give an explanation of the observed fact that S is
P? Here Aristotle refers back to his earlier investigations into logic
where he showed the validity of such classic arguments as:
Socrates is a man
All men are mortal
Socrates is mortal An
argument such as this gives us the grounds, the best possible grounds, for
believing that Socrates is mortal. It also, in Aristotle’s view, gives
us the explanation for
Socrates’s mortality. Socrates is mortal because he is a man and all men
are mortal. Generalising on this insight, Aristotle claims that arguments
of the form:
S is M
M is P
S is P provide
an explanation for the fact that S is P. Thus we say:
Why is S a P? Because S is an M, and any M is a P. Now
consider the sorts of things that make sense when we put them into the M
position (this is called the middle
term of an argument.) Aristotle thinks that all the things that can
sensibly be put in there fall into one or another of his four classes of
‘causes.’ For example: ‘why
is this statue brown?’ ‘Because it is bronze, and bronze is brown.’
That is the material cause of the brownness of the statue, and the deduction
that it fits into goes thus:
The statue is bronze
Bronze is brown
The statue is brown ‘Why
is the moon eclipsed?)’ ‘Because it is darkened by earth’s shadow,
and to be darkened by Earth’s shadow
is to be eclipsed’ That is the formal
cause. ‘Why
is the child ugly?’ ‘Because the father is ugly and ugly fathers have
ugly children.’ That is the efficient
cause, and possibly the only cause that we would actually think of as
a cause ‘Why
go walking?’ ‘Because those who want to be healthy go walking, and we
want to be healthy.’ That is the final
cause. Aristotle’s
view of scientific knowledge (epistēmē/episthmh)
was of a collection of such deductions, and we can see the implications of
this in certain statements such as that in Post.
An. 1.2 where he says: We
suppose ourselves to possess unqualified scientific knowledge of a thing,
as opposed to knowing it in the accidental way in which the sophist knows,
when we think that we know the cause on which the fact depends, as the
cause of that fact and of no other, and, further, that the fact could not
be other than it is. The last two conditions are really insisting upon the deductive form of
knowledge. If we take the explanation of the brownness of the statue for
example, having knowledge about this is being aware of the deduction from
its being a statue via the middle term of it being bronze to its being
brown. We know that the bronzeness is the cause of that fact and no other
because, given the two premises, ‘the statue is bronze’ and ‘bronze
is brown’, there is only one statement that follows inevitably to make a
valid deduction, that is that ‘the statue is brown.’ And we know that
the fact could not be other than it is because the deduction we have come
up with in the explanation is a valid deduction, and it is thus impossible
for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. Aristotle further claimed that there were conditions on the kinds of
premises that can play the explanatory role required for scientific
knowledge. He says: Assuming
then that my thesis as to the nature of scientific knowing is correct, the
premises of demonstrated knowledge must be true, primary, immediate,
better known than and prior to the conclusion, which is further related to
them as effect to cause. Unless these conditions are satisfied, the basic
truths will not be 'appropriate' to the conclusion. Deduction there may
indeed be without these conditions, but such deduction, not being
productive of scientific The point of these criteria is to eliminate trivial or irrelevant
deductions that cannot give us scientific knowledge. For example, we
don’t want to be able to say that Socrates is a man because Socrates is
a man and all men are men. That
doesn’t give us knowledge. Scientific knowledge is got only from
deductions whose premises reveal the causal nature of the world. Such
things are called demonstrations, and demonstration (apodeixis/apodeixis)
is how we get scientific knowledge. We can’t look at all these criteria here to see what role they play,
but I will make a couple of remarks. In the first place, it’s obvious
why the premises have to be true. If they weren’t true then the
demonstration might be valid but it would be unsound, and would therefore
not give us knowledge. Yes, if all men were animals and all animals were
green, then it would follow that all men are green; but of course, we
don’t know that men are green because it just isn’t true that all
animals are green. And we would have the same failure of knowledge if we
had a true conclusion but with false premises. (You might recall that I
talked about that sort of thing in the first lecture.) In the second place, when Aristotle says that the premises have to be
better known than and prior to the conclusion, he goes on to ‘clarify’
that: …
'prior' and 'better known' are ambiguous terms, for there is a difference
between what is prior and better known in the order of being and what is
prior and better known to man. I mean that objects nearer to sense are
prior and better known to man; objects without qualification prior and
better known are those further from sense. Now the most universal causes
are furthest from sense and particular causes are nearest to sense, and
they are thus exactly opposed to one another. It’s not much a clarification, I know, but what he seems to be getting
at is that some things are known more immediately to us through our senses
– like the fact that that particular triangular patch of grass is green
– but they are less certainly true, because they are not universally and
eternally true. On the other hand some things that are not known
immediately through our senses are, nevertheless, more certainly known
when they are known – like the fact that a triangle has internal angles
summing to 180o – because they are universal and eternal
truths that we come to know through reason. The criterion for causes that
we’re looking at now seems to be saying that in constructing a chain of
premises and conclusions we are trying to climb up the ladder of
generalisations, so to speak; that the causes should be more general than
the subject and predicate being explained.
|
|
Intuition and the Foundations of Scientific Knowledge |
|
There is, of course, an obvious problem with all of this. Demonstrations
are only as sound as the truth of their premises; so how do we determine
the truth of the premises, or how do we come to know the premises at all?
If we come to know them in the same scientific fashion as we come to know
the conclusions, then they will have to be the conclusions of further
demonstrations, and those demonstrations will also have premises, which we
will then have to question. And so on, apparently, ad infinitum. Eventually we have three options: i.
The chain of
premises and conclusions is infinite – and real scientific knowledge is
impossible ii.
The chain of
premises and conclusions is circular – and knowledge has no certain
foundation iii.
There is an end
to the chain of premises and conclusions at which the premises are
knowable through some other means. For
reasons which seem good to him, Aristotle is convinced that the last
option is the correct one; in which case, from what we saw just
previously, at
the very top of the chains of demonstrations that constitute the body of
scientific knowledge we have our most general concepts
which are known non-scientifically. This non-scientific knowledge he
thinks arises from our sense perceptions, and he has a fairly clear idea
of how this is supposed to happen. In the Posterior
Analytics II, 19 he says: Therefore
we must possess a capacity of some sort [for getting knowledge without
demonstration.] ... And this at least is an obvious characteristic of all
animals, for they possess a congenital discriminative capacity which is
called sense-perception. But though sense-perception is innate in all
animals, in some the sense-impression comes to persist, in others it does
not. So animals in which this persistence does not come to be have either
no knowledge at all outside the act of perceiving, or no knowledge of
objects of which no impression persists; animals in which it does come
into being have perception and can continue to retain the sense-impression
in the soul: and when such persistence is frequently repeated a further
distinction at once arises between those which out of the persistence of
such sense-impressions develop a power of systematizing them and those
which do not. So out of sense-perception comes to be what we call memory,
and out of frequently repeated memories of the same thing develops
experience; or a number of memories constitute a single experience. From
experience again – i.e. from the universal now stabilized in its
entirety within the soul, the one beside the many which is a single
identity within them all – originate the skill of the craftsman and the
knowledge of the man of science, skill in the sphere of coming to be and
science in the sphere of being. …
|
|
Investigations |
|
At
this point we know what scientific knowledge looks like: it is a structure
of demonstrations: deductions leading upwards from more general truths to
more particular truths, giving the causes of things. And we know that at
the bottom of the structure are conceptual truths that are undemonstrated
(and ‘unscientific’) which we come to know through intuition based
ultimately on our senses.
It
only remains to give a brief description of the processes by which that
structure can be built on those bases. The
first steps of this process are well enough understood and reasonably
straightforward. 1.
Collect relevant
observations of the appearances (phainomena/fainomena)
of things. This
is the obvious first step, and it simply expands upon what it is that
inspires us to take up science (or philosophy) in the first place: In Metaphysics
I, 2 (982b12-15) he remarks that
it
is owing to their wonder that men both now begin and at first began to
philosophize; they wondered originally at the obvious difficulties, then
advanced little by little and stated difficulties about the greater
matters, e.g. about the phenomena of the moon and those of the sun and of
the stars, and about the genesis of the universe. And
you will notice that Aristotle has no particular problems with simply
relying upon our senses to inform us of how the world really is. He does
not think they are infallible and he does think that they must be used
cautiously, but he obviously thinks that they are generally reliable since
that is their function. 2.
Consider the
reputable opinions (endoxa/endoxa) In
almost all of Aristotle’s works he begins by considering the opinions of
those who had gone before, to see what answers they had made to the
questions that the phenomena inspire. In the Nicomachean
Ethics VIIi
1, (1145b2–7) he says As
in other cases, we must set out the appearances and run through all the
puzzles regarding them. In this way we must test the credible opinions
about these sorts of experiences – ideally, all the credible opinions,
but if not all, then most of them, those which are the most important. For
if the objections are answered and the credible opinions remain, we shall
have an adequate proof. Aristotle
clearly thought that if lots of well-informed and sensible and trustworthy
people had a certain opinion on a matter, then it was well worth
considering it seriously. 3.
Apply dialectic It’s
unfortunate that we don’t have a consensus any longer on what is
supposed to follow: it’s currently a point of much dispute amongst
scholars of Aristotle. Surprisingly enough, the evidence of his actual
scientific works doesn’t seem to give obvious clues to the details of
his method; but one possibility is that he sees the application of the
method of dialectic as the appropriate way to sift through the possible
answers to the puzzles to arise from consideration of the phenomena. So
let’s take that to be the third step. In support of this we can quote
from Topics 101a26-b4: Dialectic
is useful for philosophical sorts of sciences because when we are able to
run through the puzzles on both sides of an issue we more readily perceive
what is true and what is false. Furthermore, it is useful for uncovering
what is primary among the commitments of a science; for it is impossible
to say anything regarding the first principles of a science on the basis
of the first principles proper to the very science under discussion, since
among all the commitments of a science, the first principles are the
primary ones. This comes rather, necessarily, from discussion of the
credible beliefs belonging to the science. This is peculiar to dialectic, or is at least
most proper to it. For since it is what cross-examines, dialectic contains
the way to the first principles of all inquiries.
|