Historical Outline | |
|
|
The General Shape of Western History |
|
Let’s
build up a general picture of the course of European history and put our
philosophers into it. First
there’s the most general view. The history of the West is typically
divided into three parts: 1.
Ancient
ends between 4-500 AD 2.
Mediaeval
(aka the Middle Ages) ends between 1400-1500 AD 3.
Modern
continues The
dates can only be given roughly because history doesn’t really
divide itself up into nice neat periods (much less into centuries!). We
divide history up this way because we think that it helps us explain and
describe historical events, but people who are interested in different
aspects of a culture will notice significant changes at different times.
Someone who is interested in political developments will say, for example,
that the Middle Ages ended with the fall of Constantinople in 1453, or the
battle of Bosworth in 1485, or some other point, while an artist might say
that the paintings of Giotto mark the beginning of a modern sensibility.
It just so happens that we note significant changes in very many aspects
of Western culture on either side of those transitional bands, hence the
standard division seems useful. The
general form of European civilization is imagined as a gradual rise to an
advanced civilization in the ancient world, followed by the collapse of
that world into barbarism with the Fall of Rome and the Barbarian
Invasions, followed by the slow recovery into an advanced pre-modern
civilization, and at last the emergence into the light of Modernity. Like
this: |
|
(Please
don’t take this too seriously!) Now
let’s look at the different periods in a little more detail
|
|
The Ancient World |
|
In
fact Ancient European history[1]
is itself divisible into three parts.
1. Minoan/Mycenaean
~2500 BC – ~1200BC
2. Greek
Dark Ages
~1200BC – ~800BC
3. Classical
Age
~800BC – ~400AD For
which we could draw very much the same sort of diagram But
we’re only interested in the last of these. The
Classical World The
Classical World is the world centred on the The
heyday of The
Greeks were pagans – we’re all familiar with their gods and myths –
and the Greek religion didn’t really have a sacred scripture such as the
Bible, but enormous respect was shown to Homer’s epics, the Iliad
and Odyssey. Every educated
person could recognise or produce a huge store of quotes from those poems.
I mention this because those poems to some extent express the ancient
cultural norms and ethical standards. (The Iliad tells the story of the
Trojan war, which took place just before the end of the Mycenaean
civilization.) The poems were formed in the barbaric period of the Greek
Dark Ages that preceded the Classical period, and so the culture in which
it is set is a barbaric, warrior culture, much concerned with honour,
fame, revenge, fate, courage,
and pride. These were values that were still held to some degree in the
later periods, and they were taken as ideals even more than they were
actually acted upon. But intelligent Greeks were well aware of the fact
that such norms, which may well have suited their primitive, Heroic
ancestors, were problematic for civilized men. In the period that we’ll
be interested in there was an effort, more or less conscious, to develop
and justify a new understanding of how Men should act together. We can see
this, for example in the ‘Oresteian Trilogy’ of plays of Aeschylus. Of
course, it’s even clearer in the work of the philosophers that we’re
going to look at, but even the philosophers had respect for those old
norms. We will see that Plato, for example, thought that a fundamental
part of the human soul was dedicated to seeking after honour, and no truly
happy human life was possible without taking that part of our humanity
into account.[2] In
the age of the city-states, however, men were more likely to agree that
the cardinal virtues were the quartet of courage
, temperance, justice, and wisdom. The
English words do not quite represent their Greek originals, and we must
not read too many associations or subtleties into them. … [I]t endured
from the sixth to the fourth century and even later; it was known to
Aeschylus, approved by Pindar, explained by Socrates, subjected to a far
reaching analysis by Plato and Aristotle, and strong enough to survive the
disintegration of Hellenism and to play a basic part in the new ethical
doctrine of the Stoics. It embodied what the Greeks admired in theory and
sought in practice, and most of them would have thought that, if a man
exercises these virtues and applies them to each situation as it arises,
he does as much as can be expected of him.[3] Note
that from what has been said, it is clear that these virtues coexisted with the more primitive ones mentioned above. I think this
is typical of how civilisations develop. The consequences of old
preoccupations need not disappear without trace when new preoccupations
arise. In the case of cultural and ethical norms, these are embodied in
the culture and continue to be transmitted for as long as there is a chain
of transmission linking the old culture to the new, and for as long as the
old preoccupations are seen as relevant to people’s lives. People are
shaped by their culture which continues to include traces of the old. One
way that I like to think of this sort of thing is as if a culture was
written on sheets of OHP slides. Each renovation of the culture is written
on a new sheet and layed over the old one. We can still see the previous
writing, but the further down it goes the fainter it gets, but perhaps it
never disappears. At the moment we’ve identified just two layers. We’ve
seen that the philosophers of the classical age endorsed the traditional
norm to some extent. But they also wanted to justify and to rationalise
it. We will see that it is characteristic of their attempts that they
begin by asking what it is that leads to a good life, and what they mean
by that is almost always: how may a man achieve happiness
in this life? It was taken for granted that happiness was the appropriate
goal of life, and that the likelihood of achieving happiness for a man was
the appropriate criterion to judge that man’s actions. For
SOCRATES, PLATO, and ARISTOTLE, this view of the pursuit of happiness was,
in general, a positive one: a man could act so as to achieve positive
benefits for himself, and this would be a good thing. For the STOICS,
however, things were not so sunny. And the reason lies in the change in
the Classical world that came about after the Classical Age. Empires
and About
300 BC the Greek world was unified by Alexander the Great. The little city
states where a man could make a difference, where a citizen could believe
that he directed the state policy, and where he could feel himself to be
the master of his fate, disappeared under Alexander’s empire and its
successors. Things became even more hopeless when This
sort of philosophy may well have suited the intellectual classes who could
take a sanguine view of their hardships, and who, increasingly, had
nothing but contempt for the old religion, but it could hardly be very
attractive to the common people of the Empire. They, indeed, soon began to
look for stronger stuff. About
the 1st centuries BC and AD there was a growing popularity of
religions that promised happiness for their believers. Sometimes this
happiness was promised in this very life and sometimes it was promised in
the afterlife, and sometime it promised both at different times. Amongst
the Roman soldiers, for example, it became common to worship the Aryan god
Mithras, or Sol Invictus (The Unconquered Sun,) while other Romans adopted
the cult of the Egyptian goddess Isis. And then, of course, there was the
religion of the Syrian god of the Christians. All of these involved gods
dying and being reborn, and all of them promised salvation. Eventually, of
course, Christianity triumphed over its rivals and the ancient paganism.
The Emperor Constantine treated Christianity as the official religion of
the With
the rise of Christianity a new set of moral beliefs came into prominence. Sin,
humility, kindness, love
of God and one’s fellow man, forgiveness,
and mercy. You’ll note that these were quite different from the
previous norms. In fact, it is a common criticism of the pre-Christian
Greek morality that there was so little of human sympathy in it. The new
norms fill in that gap and did markedly improve the quality of ethical
feeling. We also find that the Christian ethical system was in some places
directly opposed to the ancient moral system. For example, the seven
deadly sins included wrath and pride, which
were certainly not considered culpable under the pre-Christian systems. We
shall see in our treatment of the teachings of AUGUSTINE how these ethical
ideas were justified and how they were related to the other Christian
beliefs, and what consequences they had for how men were thought to be
commanded to live. One
very important aspect that I’ll mention now is the notion of a Natural Law. This was an adaptation of a Stoic view of law to the
new religion. The tendency over time was to say that since God is the
ruler of the universe, His commands are binding on us and form a
‘legal’ structure independent of human law. This wasn’t
Augustine’s view, but we’ll see what he had to say about natural and
divine law at the appropriate time. Augustine
was also concerned to explain how it could be that
[1]
History strictly refers to written records. Greek writing goes back to
perhaps 1600BC, making it the oldest recorded living language: older
even than Chinese. [2]
See C. M. Bowra (The Greek
Experience, London: Weidenfield & Nicholson, 1957; Chapter Two
– The Heroic Outlook) for much more on this. [3]
Bowra, p. 103.
|
|
The Middle Ages |
|
The
period between about 400 to about 700 was a time marked by barbarian
invasions. The Huns, Alans, Ostrogoths, Visigoths, Vandals, Franks,
Angles, and countless other tribes swarmed one after another over the
land, killing, raping, plundering, burning, and destroying. This used to
be called the ‘Dark Ages’ because there is so little written record of
the events of the time. After all barbarians tend not to record what
they’re destroying. Nowadays this terminology is felt to be
‘judgmental’. It’s also frowned upon to talk about ‘barbarians’.
But I think that no-one who knows anything about these times can have any
doubt that they were a very bad
thing. Civilisation was very nearly completely extinguished in For
a long time the Romans had tried to ease the pressure on their borders by
allowing tribes to enter and settle and become Roman. And they also tried
to use these immigrants to fight against other tribes whom they wanted to
keep or force outside the borders. This worked for a while, but eventually
the constant immigration and pressure changed the character of the
population. By the time that the Roman border finally collapsed in the
West and the barbarians began to establish kingdoms in the previous Roman
provinces, the demography and the culture of the area was sadly altered. Eventually,
of course, the barbarians began to settle down, and a new civilisation
began to form. By about 900AD to 1000AD a respectable civilisation had
once again arisen on European soil. This civilisation had a generally
feudal form and would last for about 500 years. This is the time of kings
and queens, knights on horseback, Crusades, monasteries and cathedrals.
This new civilisation, however, had a severe case of schizophrenia: it
operated according to norms derived from two quite distinct and – one
would have thought – incompatible sources. Feudalism In
the first place, the system of feudalism was the political expression of a
warrior culture that had developed from the warrior culture of the early
barbarian hordes and their early kingdoms. The ethical and cultural norms
derived from that source were similar to those that had prevailed in the
similar circumstances of the Greek Dark Ages of 2000 years earlier: men
were again much concerned with honour,
fame, revenge, courage,
and pride. But this was also slightly improved by some new elements
derived from the second source.
The
Church The
second source was the Christian faith. After the fall of In
uneasy combination with the warrior ethos this gave rise to the system of
courteous behaviour known as chivalry. It’s unfortunate that chivalry,
as the code of a warrior class, never found a real philosophical champion
– but then that would hardly be surprising either. The system itself is
recognised in the literature of the time, such as the romances of King
Arthur, or the Song of Roland or the Romance of the Rose, but
philosophical ethics derives almost entirely from the Christian source.
Nevertheless, chivalry continues to exert an influence as another layer in
our cultural heritage, and one which is surprisingly close to the surface.
For example, we say that one doesn’t kick a man when he’s down, that
one should stand up for the weak against the strong, and that women and
children should be the first on the lifeboats. We think this is normal,
but it’s not. It’s not normal in most cultures around the world today,
and it certainly wasn’t normal amongst the Greeks and Romans: they would
have found the ideas of chivalry quite alien. We
shall be studying the writings of ST THOMAS AQUINAS, who wrote towards the
end of this period, and whose works are the culmination of the scholastic
Christian philosophy, and link to the beginnings of Modern philosophy.
We’ll be particularly interested in some of his ideas on Natural and
Divine law too, since it is quite different from Augustine’s view and
leads naturally to some of the ethical ideas of the modern age.
|
|
The Modern World |
|
Chivalry
and scholasticism depended upon the political structure of feudalism, but
that type of government was fading from the world by the 15th
C. and those carriers of the Mediaeval norms had to fade with it. There is
no generally accepted marker that tells us when the Modern age begins, but
it’s generally thought that by about 1500 the world is so different from
the world of 800 that we really are talking about two different kinds of
thing, Just as 800 is so different from 100 as to be a different thing. I
won’t go into all the minor subperiods that have been identified in the
Modern Age, but two of them are really of cardinal importance because they
indicate the defining intellectual characteristic of the Modern Age. Renaissance The
very first recognised sub-period is the Renaissance, from about 1300 to
about 1600, and in that time Europeans rediscovered their heritage from
the Ancient World. There was a rebirth (that’s what ‘renaissance’
means) of the classical leaning and a renewed appreciation of the art and
literature and the ideas of the Greeks and Romans. This involved, most
significantly, a refocusing of interest in the life on Earth rather than
Heaven, and a concern with Man’s interests rather than God’s. The
Greeks and Romans you’ll recall – and contrary to the Christians of
the Middle Ages – had those interests and concerns. In this respect the
Renaissance was actually a rejection
of much of the cultural emphasis of the Middle Ages in favour of what they
imagined was the cultural emphasis of the Classical World. This all began
in the advanced city-states of Enlightenment The
second sub-period of interest is the Enlightenment of the 18th
C. This was a movement that claimed that questions were best addressed in
the light of human Reason, and that no aspect of the world would not
benefit from being exposed to this light. In particular ethical questions
and political questions were treated rationally, without reference to
revealed truth – because the various religious conflicts of the
preceding centuries had made plain just how dangerous that sort of
conflict could be. Argument and compromise are much more difficult if all
sides are convinced that they’re doing God’s Will. Again, the
continuing reaction against the culture of the Middle Ages is apparent.
The Enlightenment’s political activism reached its culmination in the
American and French Revolutions and the general acceptance amongst elites
in the West that Democracy was the proper form of government. In
the Modern World ethics has been much more concerned with supposed rights, obligations, and duties,
largely modelled on ideas that are used in explaining how law works.
Sometimes this was justified by claiming that Society itself was a
contractual relationship, and sometimes it was said that there was some
sort of Natural Law that looked and worked much like man-made law, and
sometimes it was said that the very fact of there being the possibility of
following a Law indicated that there was a Law – or something like that.
We’ll see how these concepts were treated by HOBBES, LOCKE, KANT, and
MILL. |