Aristotle on Virtue | |
|
|
Introduction |
|
Aristotle (384-322BCE) was a student of Plato and teacher of Alexander
the Great. He came to Generally speaking, philosophers everywhere can be divided into two great
groups. One group we can think of as the Idealists and Plato is the first great example of one of these. He
tended to think of the world of abstract objects as the important world,
and everything else as a mere shadow cast by the objects in the ideal
world. (There’s a famous analogy that Plato gives in his Republic
called the Allegory of the Cave[1]: there are a bunch of
people in a cave facing a wall with a light behind them; objects are
paraded behind them but in front of the light so that the shadow of the
object falls on the wall that they’re looking at. Because they’re
ignorant and it’s all they’ve seen, they think that the shadows are
the real thing. It’s the job of the philosopher to recognise this
illusion; and that’s one of the reasons why Plato thinks that
philosophers should run the ideal state – because they can see what’s really
there. They can see what’s really
good and not just what appears
to be good.) Aristotle, on the other hand, is the first great representative of the
second group, which we can call the Realists.
A realist tends to think that what’s significant in the world is the
actual world that we see, and that abstractions are secondary. We’ll see
that whereas Plato was concerned with comparing the earthly state with
some ideal model of a state which displays perfect Justice, Aristotle was
interested in seeing how people actually behaved in the world and how they
ought to behave in this world in order to achieve the things that they
want to achieve in this world. As part of this effort, Aristotle tries to
articulate what it is that people ultimately search for in life. He goes
on to develop a rich philosophical account of this life and the obstacles
we experience in trying to live it. There are two major works on Ethics by Aristotle which survive: the Nicomachean
Ethics – perhaps edited by his son Nicomachus – and the Eudemian
Ethics. The Nicomachean Ethics has been the more influential of
the two, indeed it ranks as perhaps the most influential single text in
the history of ethics, and it is this text that we examine in this lecture[2].
Our examination may begin with the title itself. You might think that
because it’s called The Ethics
and is being talked about in a course on Ethical Values, that it is quite
straightforwardly about the sort of thing that we normally call
‘Ethics;’ but you would be wrong. In fact the title in Greek is ta
ethika, which suggests our word ‘ethics’ but actually means
‘character,’ not ‘morality.’ It seems that for Aristotle, the
important thing for a man is to have the right character – and
presumably for a woman too, but as I’ve mentioned before, the Greeks
didn’t really take women seriously. Aristotle is interested in virtues,
but he is clearly opposed to the Socratic view that virtue is knowledge,
or the view that if you know what is good and right, you will
automatically do what is good and right. Being rather more realistic than
Socrates, Aristotle denies this automatic link between knowledge and
virtue. For Aristotle, to be virtuous is to have a good character, and
there is more to this than knowing what is good. A virtuous person must
have the right emotional temperament as
well as knowledge and wisdom. |
|
Moral Background |
|
Let’s consider the virtues that were current in the world that
Aristotle knew. They are, after all, the supposed motivators for
action that the society approved. You’ll recall that in the first
lecture I mentioned that the Greeks rather admired the Heroic moral
code that had prevailed in the society of the Greek Dark Ages
(~1100-900BC), or at least, they admired the version of it that had
been preserved in the Homeric poems that were supposed to be
representations of that period. You’ll recall that I mentioned that
that code was much concerned with honour,
fame, revenge, fate, courage, pride, and other such things. It was
really a code of behaviour that was centred upon honour
– the honour of the individual aristocratic warrior. Their central
moral hero – if we may call him that – was Achilles, the hero of the
Iliad. We find this just bizarre, because to our minds, the
behaviour of Achilles is far from admirable. Consider what we first
see Achilles doing in that epic: he is feuding with King Agamemnon,
because the King has claimed a woman as a prize of war that Achilles
had his eye on. He wanted to be the one to rape her and is upset that
someone else does so. He regards this as an insult, but he can’t
really attack his King, so instead he goes off to his tents to sulk,
taking all his men with him and leaving the Greek army to be thrashed
by the Trojans. This is not behaviour that is likely to impress the
modern reader, but the clue to his appeal for the Greeks lies in
another story; that he was offered a choice between a long,
commonplace life or a short, glorious one, and he chose glory. The whole emphasis of the Heroic or honour-centric life, according to the
Greek conception anyway, is on the fullest possible use of all the
qualities of body and mind. He has an image of himself which he will
not allow to be contradicted or to be denied full expression. Any
affront to this self-image must be immediately countered. It is this
attitude that explains why Achilles must behave the way he does in the
first situation: there is simply nothing in the world more important
than his own self-image and the respect it is shown by others. It is
in fact only in this way that others feature in the ‘moral’
considerations of the hero. The looked-for reward for his exertions is
the approval of others, and the disrespect of others is the mark that
he is failing. Fame is the goal of the hero at all times. You can see that the all of this seems to be concerned with the character
or the preferences of the individual man and not at all concerned with
the welfare of his community. Nevertheless, these ideals of life did
survive into the era of the city-state; and they were able to do that
to a greater degree than would otherwise be the case because they
could be made compatible with the new social order. The heroic virtues
could be placed at the service of the city rather than of the private
citizen, and yet the idea that this was an act of self-fulfilment
never disappeared. The rise of the importance of cities had another consequence, as I also
mentioned in the introductory lecture. That is that the types of
virtue that were most valued by the heroic ethos came to be supplanted
to some degree by virtues that were more appropriate to the life in a
city. As I mentioned, these newly valued characteristics included the
quartet of courage, temperance,
justice, and wisdom, and when it came time for the philosophers to
attempt to justify the moral system of their societies, it was those
sorts of virtues that they were concerned with. We’ve already seen
some examples of this, of course, when we looked at both Socrates and
Plato. Justice was, in fact, the virtue that Plato was most concerned
with, and Wisdom turned out to be pretty much synonymous with virtue
for both of them. Courage won’t concern us much – it’s a pretty
specific sort of virtue that doesn’t really lend itself to much
generalization – but temperance will.
|
|
Ethics |
|
What
we’re going to look at now is how Aristotle attempted to integrate
these seemingly very different ways of thought, and to rationalize
them so as to give them a justification beyond mere tradition. Aristotle begins the Nicomachean Ethics with a deceptively simple statement. Every
skill and every inquiry, and similarly every action and rational
choice, is thought to aim at some good; and so the good has been aptly
described as that at which everything aims.[1]
All actions aim at something. If you are doing something completely
aimless, for example day-dreaming, this won’t count as an action for Aristotle. Actions are things we do for a purpose.
Another way of putting this is to say that all actions aim at some
end. Aristotle holds that the end or purpose of our actions is always
to achieve some perceived good. Aristotle then describes a hierarchy of ends: some ends are subordinate
to others. Bridle-making has as its end making bridles. But the making
of bridles is subordinate to horsemanship in general because we make
bridles to facilitate the riding of horses; we do not ride horses in
order to facilitate the making of bridles. And horsemanship is
subordinate to military science, because we ride horses in order to
achieve victory in battle (as the Greeks would have it), we do not
seek victory in battle in order to have an excuse to ride horses.[2]
Aristotle takes this hierarchy of ends, and the sciences and arts that
facilitate their attainment, to be pervasive: all human ends fit in
the hierarchy somewhere.
Aristotle
also makes a commonsense distinction between ends that are valued
instrumentally (for example, surgery) and ends that are also valued
for their own sake. Aristotle next argues that there must be an ultimate end or supreme good
to which we aim. This is an end at the top of the hierarchy of ends.
An ultimate end is one that is valued for its own sake and is not
valued for the sake of anything else; it is something complete and
sufficient, not lacking any good. Every other end is valued,
ultimately, for the sake of this supreme good. Here is Aristotle’s
argument: So
if what is done has some end that we want for its own sake, and
everything else we want is for the sake of this end; and if we do not
choose everything for the sake of something else (because this would
lead to an infinite progression, making our desire fruitless and
vain), then clearly this will be the good, indeed the chief good.[3]
The key argument occurs in the middle of the sentence. Suppose we value
one thing for the sake of another, and that for the sake of yet
another, and that for the sake of yet another … and so on
forever. Aristotle claims our desire would be fruitless and vain (i.e.
empty). There must be one ultimate goal in our lives and if we achieve
this goal, all our other endeavours won’t have been in vain. Notice
that this isn’t at all a necessary conclusion. There’s no reason
that we couldn’t be put together in such a way that there are
several goals that are goals in themselves and that are not
instrumental for the achievement of other higher goals. It would be
easy for Plato to have argued, for example, that his study of the
human soul revealed that there were really three separate ultimate
ends corresponding to the three sources of motivation in the human
soul. The ultimate end of the appetitive soul, for example, would be
the primitive satisfaction of basic bodily needs; the ultimate end of
the ‘spirited’ soul would be the achievement and preservation of
‘honour;’ and the ultimate end of the rational soul would be
knowledge of things, or the contemplation of the knowledge of things. Aristotle can’t prove that there is only
one such goal – his argument doesn’t even attempt to show this.
But he thinks that as a matter of fact there is only one such goal.
That is, he thinks there is
one common supreme good for human beings. So, in response to someone
who claimed that there was a Platonic partition of the soul that led
to there being three distinct ultimate ends – and suppose that we
accept that those are ends that we seek – Aristotle is committed to
claiming that each of those ends is actually an instrumental end that
contributes to the satisfaction of some other more general, more
ultimate end. But what could possibly be so general, and also
universally accepted as an end, that it could possibly play that role?
It would need to be an end that subsumed bodily satisfaction, the
acknowledgement of honour, and intellectual achievement. Well,
Aristotle believes that he has a clear and obvious candidate for the
one supreme good of human life that could do this.
|
|
Eudaimonia |
|
According to Aristotle, the one ultimate end of all rational human
endeavours is happiness. Now, this sounds a bit odd at first, because
happiness doesn’t seem to be the sort of thing that, say,
intellectual achievement is appropriately seen as instrumental to. We
don’t study dead languages in order to make ourselves feel all
tingly and smiley – there are easier ways to do that. But this
oddness is only apparent, and once again, it’s mostly due to a
difficulty in translating. More strictly, we should use the Greek work
‘eudaimonia’ to describe this ultimate end. ‘Happiness’ is
close in meaning to ‘eudaimonia’, but the translation is not
precise. The sense of the term ‘happiness’ that is closest to the
meaning of ‘eudaimonia’ is that of a ‘happy life.’ This sense
of ‘happiness’ is brought out when we say of a couple that they
have a happy marriage. We
also see this usage when we claim that we have the right to ‘Life, Eudaimonia is the supreme good for human beings because: (1) it is the
ultimate end for which we pursue anything; (2) it is unconditionally
complete (we don’t seek our ultimate happiness for the sake of
anything else); and (3) it is self-sufficient (we don’t say of a
happy life that it lacks something – though of course we could
always say of a life that it could be more happy). Aristotle develops his own account of human happiness in terms of his
account of human nature. Everything has a natural ergon, or characteristic activity. For example, the ergon
of a lion seems to be to mate with other lions to produce future
generations of lions, raise cubs to such and such an age (if female)
and so on. Aristotle contends that human happiness is to be discovered
by discovering the ergon of
human beings. But
perhaps saying that happiness is the chief good sounds rather
platitudinous, and one might want its nature to be specified still
more clearly. It is possible that we might achieve that if we grasp
the characteristic activity of a human being. For just as the good –
the doing well – of a flute-player, a sculptor or any practitioner
of a skill, or generally whatever has some characteristic activity or
action, is thought to lie in its characteristic activity, so the same
would seem to be true of a human being, if indeed he has a
characteristic activity.[1] The characteristic activity of human beings is to use reason. Our
capacity to reason and everything that follows from it – including
language, technology and culture – are what distinguish us from all
other species. It is what makes us special. Thus, thinks Aristotle, it
is also the key to making us ultimately happy – in the eudaimonic
sense. One way of looking at this – and it’s what Aristotle thinks
– is that the ultimately good life is one spent just using your
reason, not by solving problems in geometry or the like, but simply in
contemplation of the things that you know. According to the
Aristotelian view the truly good life is one in which the wise man
passes in review the things that he knows in much the same way that a
connoisseur or aesthete tastes his wines one after another or
contemplates his paintings.[2]
This is a goal that no-one thinks will appeal to many people, so
perhaps Aristotle has to allow that not everyone is able to achieve
this really good life, but
there is nevertheless a version of eudaimonia that will suit everyone
and which, if they are not completely mistaken, will form the goal of
everyone’s actions in life. Another way of looking at the idea that reason is the key to ultimate
happiness is to realise that we live happily or well, only when we use
reason with great skill. The use of reason with great skill is
virtuous activity. In fact, for this and other reasons which we’ll
look at in just a moment, Aristotle does say that a
happy life is one lived according to virtue. This sounds rather
similar to Socrates’ and Plato’s views: virtue is its own ultimate
reward. But there are a couple of caveats, which make Aristotle’s
view more worldly than either Socratic or Platonic views. First
virtuous activity is accompanied by pleasure. It
is also the case that the life of [virtuous] people is pleasurable in
itself. For experiencing pleasure is an aspect of the soul, and each
person finds pleasure in that of which he is said to be fond, as a
horse-lover finds it in a horse, and someone who likes wonderful
sights finds it in a wonderful sight. In the same way, a lover of
justice finds it in the sphere of justice and in general a person with
virtue finds pleasure in what accords with virtue. The pleasures of
the masses, because they are not pleasant by nature, conflict with one
another, but the pleasures of those who are fond of noble things are
pleasant by nature. Actions in accordance with virtue are like this,
so that they are pleasant to these people as well as in themselves.
Their life therefore has no need of pleasure as some kind of lucky
ornament, but contains its pleasure in itself, because, in addition to
what we have already said, the person who does not enjoy noble actions
is not good. For no one would call a person just if he did not enjoy
acting justly, or generous if he did not enjoy generous actions; and
the same goes for the other virtues. If this is so, it follows that
actions in accordance with virtue are pleasant in themselves.[3]
Secondly, pleasure is not made identical to acting virtuously, come what
may, even when acting virtuously is pleasant. It also requires
external goods, such as health, beauty, good children, good birth:
Nevertheless,
as we suggested, happiness obviously needs the presence of external
goods as well, since it is impossible, or at least no easy matter, to
perform noble actions without resources. For in many actions, we
employ, as if they were instruments at our disposal, friends, wealth,
and political power. Again, being deprived of some things – such as
high birth, noble children, beauty – spoils our blessedness. For the
person who is terribly ugly, of low birth, or solitary and childless
is not really the sort to be happy, still less perhaps if he has
children or friends who are thoroughly bad, or good but dead. As we
have said, then, there seems to be an additional need for some sort of
prosperity like this. For this reason, some identify happiness with
good fortune, while others identify it with virtue.[4]
Aristotle also claims that what happens after one’s death can affect
one’s happiness; for instance, terrible disgrace brought about by
one’s children would mean that one couldn’t say that one had had a
happy life. This demonstrates how far Aristotle is from identifying
happiness with a kind of mental state, or indeed a function of mental
states.[5]
It’s much easier to see how
something like ‘success in life’ can be said to be affected by
events after one’s death than something like ‘pleasure.’ Finally,
we can note that Aristotle doesn’t really seem much interested in
the effects that the good life or the good man has upon the wider
society. The only thing that is really relevant to a man’s
determination of the ‘right’ thing to do or be is the effect upon
himself. You’ll see when you look at Aristotle’s investigation of
the virtues that their status as virtues is to be determined only with
respect to whether or not they contribute to the fullest possible
flourishing of the character of the agent himself. Although this seems
odd to us in a moral theory which is not explicitly a hedonistic
theory, we can see that it is quite similar to what we said about the
Heroic ethos. |
|
Virtues |
|
Their Nature It is really Aristotle’s account of the virtues that occupies the
greatest part of his book. Aristotle’s account is the most developed
in Greek philosophy and helps to make more sense of his claim (that I
mentioned above) that a happy life is a life lived according to
virtue. Once again we need to take a moment to look at the words that
we’re using, and to ask what is being talked about when a Greek
talks about ‘virtue.’ You may recall that I made some comments on
this point when we were studying Socrates. At that time I said that
the word that we translate as ‘virtue’ is the word aretę,
and that in other circumstances that word might also be translated as
‘excellence,’ or something like that. It’s a word that doesn’t
apply exclusively to humans or to moral qualities – in much the same
way that ‘good’ or ‘bad’ in English don’t. The aretę
of a thing is the way that the thing should be if it is to do what it
should do and do it well. For example, the aretę
of a knife would be its sharpness; the aretę
of an umbrella would be its coverage; that of an apple would be its
tastiness; and so on. The term has a definite flavour of a
functionalist evaluation which carries over into this supposed moral
use of the word. A virtue for a man would be that characteristic which
allows a man to be or do the thing that a man should be or do, and
this takes us back to a quote that we looked at before when Aristotle
was looking at the characteristic activities of men. Recall: For
just as the good – the doing well – of a flute-player, a sculptor
or any practitioner of a skill, or generally whatever has some
characteristic activity or action, is thought to lie in its
characteristic activity, so the same would seem to be true of a human
being, if indeed he has a characteristic activity.[1] Now, a virtue for a flute-player would be the characteristics that
contribute to the excellence of his flute-playing, and similarly for
the sculptor or the practitioners of any skill. And when we have
established that the skill at issue for man as
man is eudaimonia then we can see that the virtues that are
required are those that will contribute to the achievement of
eudaimonia. So Aristotle, like the Greeks generally, takes virtues to
be states of character, states that issue in dispositions to behave in
certain appropriate ways, experience appropriate emotions, perceive
situations and think matters through in appropriate ways, etc. This
explains to some degree the other term that Aristotle uses when he’s
trying to distinguish ‘ethical virtues,’ which is the word ‘hexis.’
This is often translated as ‘habit’ but refers to a sort of
disposition to have a kind of feeling. The Mean Much of what occupies Aristotle in his book is a detailed study of the
various characteristics that are often proposed as virtues for a man
to see whether they can qualify as virtues according to his criterion.
And it seems that most of them do, but there are qualifications that
need to be made in order to make the traditional view of things jibe
with the philosophical. He divides virtues into virtues of character
(sometimes called the ‘moral virtues’) and virtues of reason
(sometimes called the ‘intellectual virtues’). Virtues of
character involve mastering your emotions in accordance with reason.
Virtues of reason involve excellences of reason. Virtues of character
include such things as courage, temperance, generosity,
even-temperedness, magnanimity. Each is associated with a particular
feeling or a particular type of action (courage – fear; temperance
– pleasure and pain; magnanimity – giving of large donations or
gifts). Aristotle’s primary account of them is given in terms of his Doctrine
of the Mean (sometimes
also known as the via media or ‘middle way.’)
According to the doctrine of the mean, virtues lie between excess and
deficiency: First,
then, let us consider this – the fact that states like this are
naturally corrupted by deficiency and excess, as we see in the cases
of strength and health … for both too much exercise and too little
ruin one’s strength, and likewise too much food and drink and too
little ruin one’s health, while the right amount produces increase
and preserves it. The same goes, then, for temperance, courage and the
other virtues: the person who avoids and fears everything, never
standing his ground, becomes cowardly, while he who fears nothing, but
confronts every danger, becomes rash. In the same way, the person who
enjoys every pleasure and never restrains himself becomes intemperate,
while he who avoids all pleasure – as boors do – becomes, as it
were, insensible. Temperance and courage, then, are ruined by excess
and deficiency, and preserved by the mean.[2] It is important to note that Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean is not
recommending moderation in all things. Virtue may require great
feeling – anger or generosity, for instance. The mean is not an
arithmetical measure, but varies from circumstance to circumstance;
and agent to agent. An example that he uses somewhere is the
difference in the mean of appetite for a wrestler in training and for
someone who is not exerting themselves in that way. It would be
ridiculous to say that the wrestler must eat only as much as a young
girl, or vice versa. This doctrine of the Mean, however, has proved troublesome to people who
want to use it to find what they should do when they don’t already
have an idea of what they should do. Just how does one go about
applying the doctrine? How are we to know where the mean lies? When
Aristotle tries to clarify what he means by the doctrine he says
things like this: I
am talking here about virtue of character, since it is this that is
concerned with feelings and actions, and it is in these that we find
excess, deficiency and the mean. For example, fear, confidence,
appetite, anger, pity, and in general pleasure and pain can be
experienced too much or too little, and in both ways not well. But to
have them at the right time, about the right things, towards the right
people, for the right end, and in the right way, is the mean and the
best; and this is the business of virtue.[3] But such a statement, as one can plainly see, is of no real use as a
criterion of judgement. To do the right thing is to follow the mean
course in all your choices, with due allowance for circumstances; and
to follow the mean course is to do the right thing at the right time
the right way. Not useful. Not useful at all. It’s pretty clear too
that Aristotle realised that the so-called Doctrine was no good as a
criterion, because at one stage he says: We
have said that one should choose the mean … But although to say this
is true, it is not at all explicit; for in all the other occupations
about which there is a science it is true that one should exert
oneself and relax neither too much nor too little, but to a mean
extent and as the right principle dictates; but if you grasped only
this you would know nothing more – e.g. you would not know what remedies to take if someone told you to take what medical
science prescribes and as a medical man prescribes it.[4] Training Recall that virtue requires pleasure. This is important for Aristotle
(for he realises that a happy life is a pleasant one). A person truly
acts from virtue when they do so willingly, knowingly and taking
pleasure in the action. Thus a person does not truly exemplify the
virtue of courage if they act bravely – and yet terrified, hating
every moment of it. And a person does not exemplify generosity, if
they give their money away resentfully. One of the standard questions the Greeks used to ask was whether morality
could be taught. It’s not something I’ve concentrated on in
previous lectures because it hasn’t really been very relevant to our
present concerns, but Aristotle’s opinion of this matter is another
one of his claims that have given rise to endless controversy and
misunderstanding. Because Aristotle thought that virtues were forms of
character – dispositions and tendencies and so on – he also
thought that they could properly be taught, but not in the standard
intellectual way that you’ve been listening to this lecture. He
thought that a virtue could only be taught by a type of training, so
that the character in question and the actions that it would give rise
to would become a matter of habit for the good man. One develops a
virtue by acting out the virtue (copying one’s betters); eventually
coming to understand, and take pleasure in the exercise of virtue. For
example, the miserly man who wishes to be a good man, accustoms
himself to giving more generously. At first we can imagine that he
will give with clenched teeth, but as he becomes used to the action of
giving and as he begins to realise how this action is improving his
general quality of life he will come to appreciate the action and the
motivation without reservations. A cowardly man should put himself in
the way of danger until he learns how to be brave; a glutton should
stop stuffing himself; and so on. This notion has given rise to
endless quibbling that Aristotle just wants us to behave like trained
animals, and doesn’t want us to exercise our judgement in
deliberating about what to do. |