Semantics and Rhetoric | |
|
|
Semantics
and Rhetoric
|
|
I’ve
given this lecture the title of semantics and rhetoric, but for those of
you who are already familiar with these terms and with the philosophical
issues that are associated with them I have to confess that the title
promises too much: I won’t actually be dealing with how a semantic
theory could account in one fell swoop for all the facts of rhetoric.
Here the term ‘semantics’ simply refers to the meanings of words,
and I use it here as a way of organizing the discussion of some
phenomena that are important in the interpretation of arguments, and in
the evaluation of them. The term ‘rhetoric’ is my catchall term for
the miscellaneous techniques of argument presentation that are not
otherwise covered – and which look like the sort of thing that a
rhetorician might be interested in. So, it’s not so much
semantics-and-rhetoric together, as, first, some semantical stuff, and
then some rhetorical stuff.
|
|
Semantics
|
|
So let’s talk about some of the ways that an awareness of the meaningfulness of words can be significant in the interpretation of arguments. Now, you might think that the meaning of words and sentences is what we’ve been talking about for, lo, these many weeks now, and in a sense that’s right. But for the most part we’ve accepted that we understand what the words and phrases in an argument mean without too much quibbling, and what we’ve really been concentrating on is what role those words and phrases – with the assumed meanings – have been playing in the arguments. In what follows we’ll be wondering things like ‘what does that word mean in that place?’ because to identify and/or evaluate the argument under consideration we do often need to clarify crucial terms.
Vague
Terms - Indeterminate Meaning
Some
terms in an argument are such that correct limits to their application
are indeterminate or fuzzy. E.g. What exactly
counts as 'bald'? How little money do you have if you are poor? This
can sometimes lead to problems.
E.g. 'John is poor so he eligible for income support' Given that you must be quite impoverished to qualify
for income support, we really need to know how poor John is before we
can evaluate the argument. 'Poverty' is too vague to enable evaluation. You
may recognise in this the origin of the Sorites[1]
fallacy that I didn’t get time to look at last time. Let’s
look at it now. A
sorites fallacy is one in which it is claimed that two alternatives
cannot be uncontroversially distinguished, and that therefore there is
no difference between them. The
argument appears to rely upon a hidden premiss that if two concepts are
different that there is a sharp division between them.
Property P1 is defined in terms of X.
Property P2 is defined in terms of X.
X can vary by small increments. A
has property P1. [For
anything, B, with property P1, if property P1 is
different from property P2 then there is a point at which
incremental variation of X from that which defines P1 towards
that which defines P2 is sufficient to result in B having
property P2 rather than P1.] If
A has P1 and X is incrementally varied then A still has
property P1. Therefore,
there is no point at which incremental variation of X from that which
defines P1 towards that which defines P2 is
sufficient to re˙˙lt in B having property P2 rather than P1. Therefore,
P1 and P2 are not different. (That’s
looks pretty hairy itself. It makes more sense if you substitute:
P1 = ‘hairy’, P2 = ‘bald’, X =
‘number of hairs’, A = ‘Bob’)
Arguments
like this are fallacious if the hidden premiss is not true (because the
concept is genuinely vague), or if it is not obviously true and yet is
not argued for. Examples: i.
From
the moment of conception, a foetus grows and changes constantly. At each
moment it differs in only the slightest way from the previous moment.
What, then, is the exact point at which the foetus ceases to be a mere
foetus and becomes instead a person? For any point identified as the
moment when a foetus becomes a person, the foetus at that point will not
differ significantly from the foetus a moment earlier. Since we can’t
identify any moment at which a foetus becomes a person, and yet the
child is already a person when born, the foetus must be a person from
the moment of conception. ii.
All
animals have rights and we ought to respect these rights. How so? Humans
have rights, we all accept that. But what is the relevant difference
between humans and higher apes? – say the chimpanzee? Humans and
higher apes are both conscious, intelligent beings, capable of learning
and communicating through language. Apes, in turn, are closely related
to other higher mammals, higher mammals to lower mammals, and lower
mammals to other animals. Exactly where do rights come into the picture?
We cannot draw a sharp and non-arbitrary distinction between those
animals whose rights we ought to acknowledge and those we needn’t
bother with, so the rights of all animals ought to be respcted. iii.
(Robert
Nozick (1974), Anarchy, State, and
Utopia, New York: Basic Books, pp 290-292) 1.
There is a slave completely at the mercy of his brutal master’s
whims. He is often cruelly beaten, called out in the middle of the
night, and so on. 2.
The
master is kindlier and beats the slave only for stated infractions of
his rules (not fulfilling the work quota, and so on). He gives the slave
some free time. 3.
The
master has a group of slaves, and he decides how things are to be
allocated among them on nice grounds, taking into account their needs,
merit, and so on. 4.
The
master allows his slaves four days on their own and requires them to
work only three days a week on his land. The rest of the time is their
own. 5.
The
master allowes his slaves to go off and work in the city (or anywhere
they wish) for wages. He requires only that they send back to him
three-sevenths of their wages. He also retains the power to recall them
to the plantation if some emergency threatens his land; and to raise or
lower the three-sevenths amount required to be turned over to him. He
further retains the right to restrict the slaves from participating in
certain dangerous activities that threaten his financial return, for
example, mountain climbing, cigarette smoking. 6.
The
master allows all of his 10,000 slaves, except you, to vote, and the
joint decision is made by all of them. There is open discussion, and so
forth, among them, and they have the power to determine to what uses to
put whatever percentage of your (and their) earnings they decide to
take; what activities legitimately may be forbidden to you, and so on. 7.
Though
still not having the vote, you are at liberty (and are given the right)
to enter into the discussions of the 10,000, to try to persuade them to
adopt various policies and to treat you and themselves in a certain way.
They then go off to vote to decide upon policies covering the vast range of their powers. 8.
In
appreciation of your useful contributions to discussion, the 10,000
allow you to vote if they are deadlocked; they commit themselves to this
procedure. After the discussion you mark your vote on a slip of paper,
and they go off and vote. In the eventuality that they divide evenly on
some issue, 5,000 for and 5,000 against, they look at your ballot and
count it in. This has never yet happened; they have never yet had
occasion to open your ballot. (A single master also might commit himself
to letting his slave decide any issue concerning him about which he, the
master, was absolutely indifferent.) 9.
They
throw your vote in with theirs. If they are exactly tied your vote
carries the issue. Otherwise it makes no difference to the electoral
outcome. The question is: which transition from case 1 to case
9 made it no longer the tale of a slave? Ambiguity
- Multiple Meanings
Ambiguity
is, roughly, the phenomenon of multiple meaning. When something is
uttered or written it is often said to be ambiguous
when it admits of multiple interpretations or admits of multiple
meanings. It can arise with regard to utterances or the words of phrases
uttered. More
exactly, there are two senses in which we might describe an utterance
or word or phrase as ambiguous: 1.
An utterance, word or phrase is ambiguous(1)
if and only if it has more than one
meaning.
E.g.
'bank'; 'found by some cows'; etc. 2. An
utterance, word or phrase is ambiguous(2)
in a given context C if and only if it is misleading or potentially
misleading because it is difficult to tell which of a number of possible
meanings is intended in context C.
E.g.
the term 'person' in a debate on abortion; 'family' in public
funding debates ·
Notice
that an utterance, word or phrase is ambiguous2
only if it is ambiguous1
— for multiple meanings to constitute a problem (ambiguity2) there must be multiple meanings (ambiguity1).[2] ·
We
shall generally be interested in ambiguity as a defect, so the relevant
sense is sense-2. It is only when multiple meanings are potentially
misleading that fallacies arise. ·
multiple
meanings can cause problems in even determining what the argument under
consideration is.
— pronouns
E.g.
'John is still sick so he will be charged'
Does 'he' refer to 'John' or someone else? E.g. is the argument:
John is still sick
or
John is still sick
John will be charged
John's
doctor will be charged
We should be careful to fill out pronoun
expressions since, once out of the context of
the surrounding discussion, their meaning might be unclear.
In fact, words like 'here', 'now', 'he', 'I' should all be
replaced by what they refer to.
— scope of claim
E.g. 1
'The early deaths of Joplin and Hendrix show how really
dangerous drugs are'
Is this argument:
Joplin and Hendrix died early (from drug-overdose)
or Joplin
and Hendrix ...
Some drugs are really
dangerous
All drugs are ...
E.g. 2
'Judges voted Volkswagen the best car of 2001' Given this understanding of ambiguity we can now make a further distinction based on the observation that because the meaning of a phrase can be seen as arising from the meanings of the individual words therein and the way they are structured, both individual word-meaning and structure can be a possible cause of ambiguity. The obvious consequence of this is that ambiguity must come in two forms.
1.
Verbal or Semantic Ambiguity (Lexical Ambiguity)
Most
of the examples of ambiguity that we usually identify are examples of
words that are ambiguous. This is generally referred to as semantic
or lexical ambiguity. Another example is the claim:
'OJ Simpson had his golf clubs taken from him to fund
compensation for his wife's family' Does
this mean he had his wedge, five-iron, and other "ball-hitting
implements" taken, or did he have the profit-making organisations
of which golf players are members taken?
Fallacy
of Equivocation (again) You’ll
probably remember that we had a quick look at how this sort of ambiguity
can affect arguments last week in the section on ‘fallacies’. There
we said that an argument involves the fallacy of equivocation
when it exploits the different meanings of a word in different parts of
the argument (typically, in different premises) to make the argument
appear good when it is not. E.g. A simple, clear
example from the Text is:
Six is an odd number of legs for a horse
Odd numbers cannot be divided by two
Six cannot be divided by two. The word 'odd' is used in two senses — odd1
= unusual; odd2
= not even — and the argument gains any strength it has by ignoring
this. The argument might be clarified as follows: Six is an odd1
number of legs for a horse
Six is an odd2 number of legs for a horse Odd2
numbers cannot be divided by two
OR
Odd2
numbers cannot be divided by two
Six cannot be divided by two.
Six cannot be divided by two. ·
With
the meanings of the terms clarified so as to make the premises true (see
the argument above right), there is little risk of thinking that they
provide any support for the conclusion since the argument obviously
equivocates. ·
With
the meanings of the terms clarified so as to make the conclusion follow
from the premises (see the argument above right), there is little risk
of thinking all the premises are true. E.g. Less obviously,
consider the following argument, seemingly implicit in remarks by a
recent Prime Minister, in defence of the particular way spending cuts
were distributed in a recent Budget. Cuts were made equally across all
(A)
I cannot be criticised for fairly distributing a necessary burden
(B)
The budget cuts were a necessary burden fairly distributed
I cannot be criticised for the budget cuts
The notion of a 'fair distribution' is ambiguous, meaning:
1.
distributed equally across all
2.
distributed across all according to their capacity.
For the argument to be valid it must use the notion in one sense
throughout, BUT:
— if sense 1 is the intended sense then premise B looks true
but premise A seems
vulnerable. (Fairness might, arguably, require each person
contribute according to
their capacity; the rich should, on this view, contribute more
than the poor.)
— if sense 2 is the intended sense then premise A may be
thought true (for the reasons just
given) but (given the way cuts were actually effected) premise B
now seems
vulnerable. ·
With
the meanings of the terms clarified so as to make both premises true,
there is little risk of thinking that they provide any support for the
conclusion since the argument obviously equivocates. · With the meanings of the terms clarified so as to make the conclusion follow from the premises, there is little risk of thinking all the premises are true.
General
Strategy for Diagnosis
Where
one suspects equivocation within an argument: (a)
spell out the various senses of the term involved (b)
restate the argument so that no equivocation occurs (c) evaluate each clarified argument. (If there is a fallacy of equivocation, none will be compelling.)
2.
Grammatical or Syntactic Ambiguity (Amphiboly)
A
phrase can be ambiguous due to the structure of the phrase. Such cases
are referred to as cases of syntactic ambiguity or amphiboly. E.g. —
Wartime poster:
SAVE SOAP AND WASTE PAPER
—
Definition of anthropology:
THE SCIENCE OF MAN EMBRACING WOMAN
—
Newspaper headlines:
FLYING PLANES CAN BE DANGEROUS MAN BLOWS OUT HIS BRAINS AFTER TAKING AFFECTIONATE
FAREWELL OF HIS FAMILY WITH A SHOTGUN
—
Philosophy:
EVERYTHING MUST HAVE SOME CAUSE Fallacy
of Amphiboly An
argument is said to commit the fallacy of amphiboly just in case
its apparent strength rests on reading a syntactically ambiguous phrase
in the premises in one sense to ensure their truth and another sense to
support the conclusion. E.g. He was found in the ditch by some cows Everything must have some cause Cows can find people. Some one thing must be the cause of everything
General
Strategy for Diagnosis
Where
one suspects amphiboly within an argument: (a)
spell out the various senses of the syntactically ambiguous phrase
involved (b)
restate the argument so that no equivocation occurs (c) evaluate each clarified argument. (If there is a fallacy of amphiboly, none will be compelling.)
Jargon
- Unknown Meaning
Arguments
often involve jargon-terms — that is, terms with specialised meaning
in a particular area. E.g.
'materialism' as used by
philosophers means something quite specialised and something different
from another common use of the term to describe someone who likes
material comforts. E.g.
The notion of 'clear and distinct understanding' as used by
Descartes means something quite specialised (scholarship is required to
discern meaning). Consequently,
it can be difficult to evaluate an argument if it contains such a term
whose meaning you do not know. This problem is solved by finding (by
scholarship) or giving (by stipulation) a clear meaning to the jargon
term so that all parties to the argument can see what is meant. Definitions
To
avoid problems surrounding the use of ambiguous terms in reasoning or
terms whose meaning is simply unclear, one can — and, in disciplines
like philosophy, often does — define
a clear and unambiguous meaning for a term or phrase. Definitions are of
various kinds. (The
book gives a list, but here is one which, I think, is clearer.) In
the first instance we can broadly divide kinds of definitions into those
which are used to describe current meanings (lexical definitions) and
those which are used to attach new meanings (stipulative definitions). A.
Lexical Definitions
Definitions which report current, conventional meanings for terms Examples: 1.
Dictionary Definitions Such definitions generally provide
statements of conventionally accepted meanings of words which, though
suitable for everyday purposes, are somewhat loose, inexact or
incomplete. (Accordingly, the problem with their use in academic
writing, to support a particular interpretation of a term in argument
(say), is that the subtle shades of meaning on whichyourargument might
depend may either be unspecified by the dictionary, or specified
according to conventional usage but conventional usage might be
misguided on the matter).
[See Cederblom, p. 199 for inadequacies of such definitions.]
Other kinds of definition which can also be used to give lexical
definitions include: 2.
Denotative or Ostensive Definitions
Giving the collection or class of things to which the term may be
correctly applied, or
paradigmatic examples of things to which it applies.
E.g.
By Eucalypts I mean Red
Gums, Coolibahs, etc. (listing eucalypts)
By mental events I mean
things like desires and beliefs. 3.
Logical Definitions
Giving the set of conditions met by all and only those objects to
which the term applies.
I.e. giving the set of criteria necessary and sufficient for the
application of the term.
E.g.
By a square I mean any
equal sided rectangle.
Something is a square
if and only if it is an equal sided rectangle.
A good logical definition is neither too broad nor too narrow; is
not circular; uses clearly
understood terms; is not negative when it can be affirmative. The
foregoing kinds of definition might be employed to report the current
meaning of a term. On the other hand, definitions might be used to
give new meaning to a term. B.
Stipulative Definitions
Attaching unconventional, new meaning to a term.
Ordinarily one stipulates a meaning when:
(a) one believes that a word is ambiguous and seeks to forestall
any possible equivocation; or
(b) one finds that no word exists for a concept to be used.
E.g.
(a) "For the purposes of this debate let us use democracy
to mean ..." (b) "Let bleen
be that property that something has just if it is blue until the year
2000 and green thereafter." Examples:
Denotative or Ostensive Definitions
(see above)
Logical Definitions
(see above)
A potentially problematic
aspect of stipulative definition is:
Persuasive Definition
Attaching a different literal meaning to a word while preserving
its old emotional or
evaluative impact. E.g. Defining the
"true" Australian as someone who cares about the plight of
farmers; or defining "right-thinking people" as those against
fluoridation of drinking water. Sometimes, rather than eliminating ambiguity, this
type of definition reintroduces it, leading to the problem of
redefinition. That is where someone uses the persuasive definition
of a term so that it applies to a desired group yet has all the
emotional or evaluative impact of the term as originally understood.
E.g.
All right-thinking people are against fluoridation
Reasonable people are right-thinking
Reasonable people are against fluoridation The first premise of this argument is true given the
above persuasive definition. (It is in fact a truism, amounting to the
claim "All people against fluoridation are against
fluoridation"). However, in this sense of "right-thinking
person" the second premise is questionable. This premise might
appear true because we may be tempted to attach the original evaluative
impact to the term "right-thinking person". The argument appears compelling only if one equivocates
between the new stipulated meaning of "right-thinking person"
and the original meaning of the phrase.
[1] I should also mention here that the term ‘sorites’ is also applied to a type of argument quite different from this sorites paradox/fallacy. A sorites is an argument in which no single syllogistic inference can take us from the premisses to the conclusion, but in which a chain of syllogisms will do so. For example:
All A are B, all B are C, all C are D; so all A are D. [2] Notice also that, given these two senses of 'ambiguous', the term 'ambiguous' is itself amibiguous1. It is ambiguous2 just in case the ambiguity is potentially misleading in some context. If we were able to go on and say that the term 'ambiguous' was itself ambiguous, pure and simple, (rather than ambiguous1 ) then we would be justified in saying the term was self-describing. That is to say, in more technical jargon, 'ambiguous' would be an homological term—a term which applies to itself like 'polysyllabic' (which is itself polysyllabic). Its homological nature would then contrast with those terms which are not homological but, rather, heterological‑like 'monosyllabic' (which is not self-describing, is not monosyllabic but is, instead, polysyllabic).
|
|
Rhetoric
|
|
So much for that short treatment of how the ‘meanings’ of words and phrases can be abused in arguments. Now we shall turn to those techniques that don’t fit quite so neatly into such a classification but which are nevertheless of some significance in affecting the effectiveness of arguments. I call these things ‘rhetoricisms’ for my own convenience, but you’re quite welcome to reject this term as an impossibly ugly neologism.
Irrelevancies
Text
or conversations containing arguments almost always contain a great deal
which is not part of the contained argument. Some of it might be by way
of introduction, helpful asides, discounting, etc. Much of this is
useful in the presentation of
an argument. However, when it comes to analysing
an argument, this material is often dropped since it does not constitute
part of the argument's premises, intermediary conclusions, or overall
conclusion. There
are probably an infinite number of ways in which we can imagine that
parts of a text being presented to us as an argument are irrelevant.
Here are just a couple which seem to be particularly popular: a.
going off on tangents
to gain argumentative advantage. This
often appears upon closer examination to be merely excessive verbiage. E.g.
Q: 'Should the government's tax changes be accepted?' A:
'The government has a lousy record on tax change. These
changes are unnecessary because […]' The
argument is simply:
[…]
The government's tax changes are unnecessary An
extreme case is where someone is asked why we should believe their claim
X, and in fact no argument is
offered at all! The point is avoided, not addressed. When the excess
verbiage is eliminated as a mere tangent, nothing remains. b.
repetition E.g. '… because it is wrong; it's immoral;
it's obscene!' In
extreme cases repetition actually takes the place of argument. When
repetitious claims are eliminated, sometimes only a single assertion of
the very point at issue remains. This is a commonly employed rhetorical
device (i.e. a device for producing good rhetorical argument). The
audience may as a matter of psychological fact become convinced of some
claim A if its assertion is repeated often enough, even in the absence
of good reasons or argument for believing it. Assuring, guarding and discounting are three strategies commonly used to secure acceptance of premises or reasons as true.
Assuring
·
Presenting
reasons that are "assuredly true" ... to convince a
disbelieving audience.
— by citing authority as an assurance
E.g.
"Economists agree that ..."
— by showing you yourself accept them
E.g.
"There is no doubt that ..."
(conversationally implying there are reasons)
— by citing obviousness
E.g.
"Clearly ..."
(implying that disbelief amounts to
ignorance) In
honest argumentation assurances may save time by referring
audience to further argument not presented but available. In dishonest argumentation they may be used to cover weak points in an argument.
Irrelevant assuring
E.g.
'You obviously cannot play golf in Alaska in January so there's
no point in bringing your clubs'
You cannot play golf in Alaska in January
There's no point in
bringing your clubs But
assuring is not always
irrelevant. E.g.
'You obviously cannot play golf in Alaska in January so there should be
no thought of your bringing your clubs'
You obviously cannot play golf in Alaska in January
There should be no thought of you bringing your clubs Guarding
·
Presenting
reasons that are suitably weakened by ...
—
restricting scope or extent of claims - less general
E.g. "Some ..." instead of "All ..."
—
retreating from certain claims to merely probable claims - less
certain
E.g. "Evidence suggests that ..." instead of "It
is plainly the case that ..."
—
retreating from knowledge-claims to belief-claims - less
dogmatic
E.g. "I now think that ..." instead of "I know
that ..." In
honest argumentation guarding may yield reasons which are more
believable. Don't
commit yourself to claims stronger than you need ... but don't go too
weak — find a "middle way".
In dishonest argumentation guarding often functions to cover the reasoner by only making explicit a claim that can be defended whilst perhaps encouraging the audience the accept the conversationally implied stronger claim. (Anecdotal evidence is often used in this way. One explicitly says that people have suggested that X, conversationally implying X.)
Irrelevant guarding
E.g. 'I think
Miranda is at home so we can meet her there'
Miranda is at home
We can meet her there But
guarding is not always
irrelevant to the argument. E.g. 'I think Miranda is at
home so I don't expect to see her at University today'
I think Miranda is at home
I don't expect to see her
at University today Discounting
·
Dispelling
doubts surrounding reasons by citing possible criticism only to discount
it. E.g. 'Since historically public debt leads to
inflation, I maintain that, despite recent trends,
inflation
will return' [from Exercise VI #2, Ch 2]
The argument is
simply:
Historically public debt leads to inflation
Inflation will return E.g. The
ring is beautiful but
expensive [… so let's not buy it.]
(Discounting its beauty)
The ring is
expensive but beautiful [… so let's buy it.]
(Discounting the expense) A but B
A although B
(i)
asserts A
(v)
asserts A
(ii)
asserts B
(vi)
asserts B
(iii)
suggests A/B opposition
(vii)
suggests A/B opposition
(iv)
A discounted by B
(viii)
B discounted by A
Discounting
A
Discounting B
A but B
A although B
A however B
A
(even) though B
A nonetheless B
A even if B
·
Discounting
is useful for:
(a)
pre-empting moves by opponent
(b)
blocking conversational implication
(c)
avoiding side issues or tangents ·
Discounting
can be abused by:
(a)
pre-empting easy objections to hide or bury difficult ones
(b)
using it to imply that opponent holds some crazy view (by means
of (iii)
above
- the suggested opposition) E.g. I agree that pollution is bad but stopping all industry won't work.
Evaluative
Language (vs Descriptive)
The
use of evaluative language is often important in pushing an argument
through and for that reason we must be aware of its use.
·
Evaluative
terms like 'good', 'proper', 'efficient' or 'beautiful' are typically
said to invoke (positive, virtuous) standards against which
"things" (e.g. objects, events, etc.) can be evaluated. Since
such evaluations go beyond a mere description of how things are, they
can be contested in a way that mere description cannot be. You can
disagree with someone who describes a particular act as one that is good
in a way that you cannot if they merely report the act itself. The standards of evaluation
can be vague, and may vary culturally but
imprecision and variation do not show that there are no shared
standards, that it is merely a matter of taste. ·
Recognising
evaluative use of language is important but can be difficult. Test: Does the use
mean something is good or bad; right or wrong; ought be done or ought
not. E.g. 'homicide' vs
'murder'
'refugee' vs 'illegal immigrant'
'removed' vs 'stolen' Euphemism
and Spin Doctoring
·
Euphemism — The use of language to describe something in more gentle or
favourable terms. E.g. "It's only
downsizing, so it's not anything to be concerned about." · The euphemism should in many cases be scrutinised.
Figurative
Language
·
Language
is not always used in its literal sense but metaphorically. E.g. a glaring
mistake Arguments may sometimes
contain figurative language where the conclusion is backed up by
reliance on some metaphor.
E.g.
The High Court is a court of autocratic kings
We can and should ignore their decisions ·
Criticism
naturally focuses on the appropriateness of the metaphor |