There are good arguments and there are bad arguments. In this course we’ve assumed that the ‘goodness’ of an argument – considered as a technique by which people are to be persuaded of some proposition – is captured by the notion of ‘effectiveness. That is, that an argument is good/effective for a respondent if it is such that the argument leads to an increased disposition in the respondent to accept the conclusion of an argument if they accept the premisses of an argument. In the last few lectures we’ve been looking at one very important way in which arguments can be good or effective arguments. We have seen that valid arguments are the ultimately effective arguments. They are as effective or as good as any argument could possibly be because they have the tendency to create an irresistible urge to accept the conclusions given the premisses. (And we’ve also recognised in certain formal properties of arguments ways in which if an argument that is valid is not absolutely convincing as it is presented, it can be altered without changing its meaning to be absolutely convincing.) But we’ve always been aware that there are many other types of effective argument of varying strength. Those arguments that talk about the happy Australian, for example.
The ‘happy Australian’
arguments are special case that we’re going to come back to in later lectures.
In this lecture we’re going to be looking at some other types of argument that
are effective and which are not valid. The arguments we’ll be looking at
achieve effectiveness by means of various specific techniques as we’ll see, but
they are all marked by a common feature: that they attempt to disguise
themselves as valid arguments. In this disguise they arouse our argument intuition
in its strongest form, but once we see through their disguise we are in a
position to resist the temptations which they present, because we now recognise
the types of arguments that they really are – and they are not the sorts of
arguments that arouse those argument intuitions. They are – in that respect –
illegitimate arguments. These arguments are assigned the pejorative label
‘fallacy’ and they fall into two general categories, formal and informal, the
first of which is the least interesting.
We’ve
already had a look at two very common errors in arguments related to the
formally valid arguments. We called them formal fallacies because they
result from an error in the very form of the argument. But they are fallacies
because they are often effective and it can sometimes take some effort to see
just why they should not be absolutely effective – ie. valid. And it isn’t until
we see that they are invalid that they lose this effectiveness.
1.
Affirming the
Consequent
If A then B + B
A
Example:
If
you are English then you like fish and chips.
You
like fish and chips.
------------------------------
So,
you are English.
2.
Denying the
Antecedent
If A
then B + Not A
Not B
Example:
If
you are English then you like fish and chips.
You
are not English.
------------------------
So,
you do not like fish and chips.
There is no widely accepted categorization of informal
fallacies. This is my own attempt at a catalogue
raisonné.
1.
Begging the
question
Also known as petitio principii or circular
argument.
Note that the offensive reason may be a hidden
premiss.
Such arguments have the form:
1 (+ ?)
…
1
Note
that the form of the argument is actually good. A question-begging argument is
formally valid because ‘A, therefore A’ is always going to be true.
Examples:
i.
‘The
Bible says God exists. Everything in the Bible is true, because God wrote it.
So God exists.’
ii.
‘Australia’s
present constitution is the best guarantee of stable government because it is
the constitution which best protects us from governmental instability.’
iii.
‘It’s
wrong to murder people. Capital punishment involves murdering people. So
capital punishment is wrong.’
2.
Equivocation
An
ambiguous word is used in two different ways in an argument and the
acceptability of the argument depends upon not noticing that difference.
An
equivocating argument may appear to be valid, eg. if the argument relies upon
an equivocation in the word ‘Q’, then we might see the argument as:
All
P are Q + All Q are R
All P are R
But
if the equivocation is made clear and Q is replaced by the synonym Q1
for one use and the synonym Q2 for the other use, then the apparent
validity disappears because the argument looks like:
All
P are Q1 + All Q2 are R
All P are R
Which is no good.
Examples:
i.
‘The
laws of nature must have a lawmaker because they are laws, and all laws have a
lawmaker.’
ii.
‘Nothing
is better than eternal heavenly bliss; and a Big Mac™ is better than nothing.
Thus a Big Mac™ is better than heaven.’
iii.
‘Six
is an odd number of legs for a horse. Odd numbers are not divisible by two. Six
is not divisible by two’
3.
Straw Man
Argument directed against an inaccurate statement of
the opponent’s position
Examples:
i.
‘The
theory of evolution states that humans are no different from apes, but humans
are clearly smarter than apes, so the theory of evolution is wrong.’
ii.
‘People
who believe we should spend less on defence apparently believe that the
instability in the former Soviet Union and Africa poses no threat to our
interests.’
iii.
‘I’m
in favour of legalised gambling. There are those who oppose it, but they
apparently believe that anything that’s fun is sinful.’
4.
Slippery
Slope fallacy
An
argument against a proposed action which claims that it will very probably
lead to bad consequences is a s. s. fallacy if the claim of high probability is
not supported. (If the claim is supported then it is not a s. s. fallacy
but a good s. s. argument.)
Examples:
i.
‘Legalised
voluntary euthanasia sounds fine, but inevitably the conditions for euthanasia
will be loosened. First, incurable terminal diseases will be included, then
merely debilitating conditions, then expensive-to-treat illnesses, then simply
inconvenient illnesses will qualify.’
ii.
‘First
they’ll ask for guns to be registered, then they’ll want to institute a licence
test, then they’ll ban certain weapons, then they’ll take them all away, and
we’ll be quite defenceless.’
iii.
‘It’d
be a mistake to try to recreate the welfare programs of the 60s and 70s. If you
give people something, they’ll come to expect it, and then to regard it as a
right. Who would then work rather than sit back and be paid.’
5.
False Dilemma
One
of the reasons supporting the conclusion is a false (or inadequately argued)
division of possibilities into a dichotomy. Such arguments have the form:
A
or B + not A
B
Notice
that this is a valid argument. What makes it a fallacy is the falsehood of the
choice that is taken as a premiss.
Examples:
i.
‘Don’t
vote for the bill requiring a deposit on bottles. There’s lots of litter other
than bottles; we should require a deposit on all potential litter or on none.’
ii.
‘You’re
either part of the solution, or part of the problem.’
iii.
‘Either
we ban all guns or we let crime run amok.’
6.
Argumentum ad
hominem
A
personal attack is made on someone, and that attack is taken to be a reason for
rejecting the argument that they are putting forward. Generally, such
arguments, where they are not purely abusive (and are thus perhaps poisoning
the well or ad baculum) are attempting to undermine the assumption that
the person being attacked is participating in the argument in good faith. In
such uses there may be a suppressed argument roughly like:
1(Attack on A)
a
[A is not trustworthy] + 2[believe someone iff they
are trustworthy]
A says that X + [don’t believe what A says]
Don’t
believe that X
There
are legitimate as well as illegitimate (fallacious) ad hominem
arguments. What distinguishes the two is typically the strength of the
inference (a), and the truth of (1), and also whether the hidden premiss (2) is
reasonable in the context of the argument.
Examples:
i.
Abusive: ‘We have to act now to
save the forests.’
‘You would think that, you’re a hippy.’
ii.
Circumstantial: ‘We should develop normal
relations with Cuba.’‘You only say that because you want to make money selling
their fancy cigars.’
iii.
Tu quoque: ‘You’re telling me I
should drink less? You haven’t been sober in a year!’
7.
Genetic
fallacy
Closely
related to the ad hominem argument.
There
are always reasons why someone holds the beliefs they do. These reasons are to
be distinguished from the justifications which they might offer for holding
these beliefs. (Eg. A Catholic may believe in God because he was brought
up that way, but he may justify his belief in God by revelation or
philosophical argument.) A genetic fallacy is committed if one attacks the causes
of a belief rather than the justifications for it.
Examples:
i.
‘Studies
show that passive smoking is quite harmless.’
‘Those studies were all commissioned and funded by
cigarette companies.’
ii.
‘The
best system of insurance includes a type of no-fault policy.’
‘That’s a type of insurance policy being promoted by
the insurance companies themselves. I’m sure it can’t be good for their
customers.’
iii.
‘Psychiatric
hospitals arose from an attempt to control disruptive elements, not to help
them. We should eliminate them.’
8.
Authority
Appealing
for support to someone whose authority (if any) is not relevant to the matter
in question. Notice the similarity in the suppressed argument that seems to lie
behind this fallacy to that which lies behind the fallacy of argumentum ad
hominem:
1(A is
an authority)
a
[A is trustworthy] + 2[believe
someone iff they are trustworthy]
A says that X + [believe what A says]
Believe
that X
There
are legitimate as well as illegitimate (fallacious) arguments from authority.
What distinguishes the two is typically the strength of the inference (a), and
the truth of (1), and also whether the hidden premiss (2) is reasonable in the
context of the argument.
Examples:
i.
‘Can
you doubt that air has weight when you have the clear testimony of Aristotle
affirming that all the elements have weight including air, and excepting only
fire.’
ii.
‘I’m
not a doctor but I play one on TV.’
iii.
‘A
majority of doctors think that the morality of young people has declined.’
9.
Ignorance (Argumentum ad ignorantiam)
Claiming
that something is true because it has not been proved to be false, or false
because it has not been proved to be true.
Such
arguments rely upon a hidden premiss and have the forms:
‘A’ is not proved + [If ‘A’ was true it would have
been proved]
‘A’ is not
true
‘not A’ is not proved + [If ‘A’ was false, ‘not A’ would have been
proved]
‘A’ is
true
These
are fallacies when the hidden premiss is obviously false, or if it is not
obviously true and yet is not argued for.
Examples:
i.
‘My
wife must be having an affair since I can’t prove that she isn’t.’
ii.
‘Since
no one has been able to prove God’s existence, God does not exist.’
iii.
‘Since
no WMD’s have been found, there were never any WMDs.’
10.
Motivational
Appeals
Attempting
to induce someone to accept a conclusion by appealing to motives rather than
providing reasons to think that the conclusion is true.
Examples:
i.
Force (Threat, Fear,
Argumentum ad baculum): ‘You should not put smoking bans in your restaurants because if you
do we smokers will boycott you, and we are a large part of your customer base.’
ii.
Pity (Argumentum ad
misericordiam):
‘I am qualified for this job – I have some expeience and I need the money to
get my baby sister into the eye-hospital.’
iii.
Prejudicial (Poisoning the
well):
‘Would anyone be so naďve as to doubt that the finest painters were French?’
11.
Sorites
Claiming
that two alternatives cannot be uncontroversially distinguished, and that
therefore there is no difference between them.
The
argument appears to rely upon a hidden premiss that if two concepts are
different that there is a sharp division between them.
Property
P1 is defined in terms of X.
Property P2 is defined in terms of X.
X can vary by small increments.
A has
property P1.
[For anything, B, with property P1, if
property P1 is different from property P2 then there is a
point at which incremental variation of X from that which defines P1
towards that which defines P2 is sufficient to result in B having
property P2 rather than P1.]
If A has P1 and X is incrementally varied
then A still has property P1.
Therefore, there is no point at which incremental
variation of X from that which defines P1 towards that which defines
P2 is sufficient to result in B having property P2 rather
than P1.
Therefore, P1 and P2 are not
different.
(That’s looks pretty hairy itself. It makes more sense
if you substitute:
P1
= ‘hairy’, P2 = ‘bald’, X = ‘number of hairs’, A = ‘Bob’)
Arguments
like this are fallacious if the hidden premiss is not true (because the concept
is genuinely vague), or if it is not obviously true and yet is not argued for.
Examples:
i.
From
the moment of conception, a foetus grows and changes constantly. At each moment
it differs in only the slightest way from the previous moment. What, then, is
the exact point at which the foetus ceases to be a mere foetus and becomes
instead a person? For any point identified as the moment when a foetus becomes
a person, the foetus at that point will not differ significantly from the
foetus a moment earlier. Since we can’t identify any moment at which a foetus
becomes a person, and yet the child is already a person when born, the foetus
must be a person from the moment of conception.
ii.
All
animals have rights and we ought to respect these rights. How so? Humans have
rights, we all accept that. But what is the relevant difference between humans
and higher apes? – say the chimpanzee? Humans and higher apes are both
conscious, intelligent beings, capable of learning and communicating through
language. Apes, in turn, are closely related to other higher mammals, higher
mammals to lower mammals, and lower mammals to other animals. Exactly where do
rights come into the picture? We cannot draw a sharp and non-arbitrary
distinction between those animals whose rights we ought to acknowledge and
those we needn’t bother with, so the rights of all animals ought to be
respcted.
iii.
(Robert
Nozick (1974), Anarchy, State, and Utopia,
New York: Basic Books, pp 290-292)
1. There is a slave completely at the mercy of his brutal
master’s whims. He is often cruelly beaten, called out in the middle of the
night, and so on.
2.
The
master is kindlier and beats the slave only for stated infractions of his rules
(not fulfilling the work quota, and so on). He gives the slave some free time.
3.
The
master has a group of slaves, and he decides how things are to be allocated
among them on nice grounds, taking into account their needs, merit, and so on.
4.
The
master allows his slaves four days on their own and requires them to work only
three days a week on his land. The rest of the time is their own.
5.
The
master allowes his slaves to go off and work in the city (or anywhere they
wish) for wages. He requires only that they send back to him three-sevenths of
their wages. He also retains the power to recall them to the plantation if some
emergency threatens his land; and to raise or lower the three-sevenths amount
required to be turned over to him. He further retains the right to restrict the
slaves from participating in certain dangerous activities that threaten his
financial return, for example, mountain climbing, cigarette smoking.
6.
The
master allows all of his 10,000 slaves, except you, to vote, and the joint
decision is made by all of them. There is open discussion, and so forth, among
them, and they have the power to determine to what uses to put whatever
percentage of your (and their) earnings they decide to take; what activities
legitimately may be forbidden to you, and so on.
7.
Though
still not having the vote, you are at liberty (and are given the right) to
enter into the discussions of the 10,000, to try to persuade them to adopt
various policies and to treat you and themselves in a certain way. They then go
off to vote to decide upon policies covering the vast range of their powers.
8.
In
appreciation of your useful contributions to discussion, the 10,000 allow you
to vote if they are deadlocked; they commit themselves to this procedure. After
the discussion you mark your vote on a slip of paper, and they go off and vote.
In the eventuality that they divide evenly on some issue, 5,000 for and 5,000
against, they look at your ballot and count it in. This has never yet happened;
they have never yet had occasion to open your ballot. (A single master also
might commit himself to letting his slave decide any issue concerning him about
which he, the master, was absolutely indifferent.)
9.
They
throw your vote in with theirs. If they are exactly tied your vote carries the
issue. Otherwise it makes no difference to the electoral outcome.
The question is: which transition from case 1 to
case 9 made it no longer the tale of a slave?
12.
False Analogy
Arguing
faultily that because two things have certain similarities they will also have
other similarities.
An
argument from analogy generally looks like this:
1.
It is claimed that the Object
(an argument, or a natural phenomenon, or an idea, or what you will) has
properties P1, P2, …, Pn.
2.
The Analogue also
has properties P1, P2, …, Pn.
3.
The analogue has
property P.
4.
Therefore the object has
property P.
The
argument relies upon the hidden premiss that
[5. If
two objects share properties P1, P2, …, Pn,
they will also share property P.]
Arguments
like this are fallacious if the hidden premiss is not true or if it is not
obviously true and yet is not argued for.
Examples:
i.
A
country is like a ship with the president as the captain. Just as the captain
should be obeyed without question during a storm, the president should be given
special powers in periods of crisis.
ii.
The
finances of a government are like the finances of a family. A family can’t go
on spending more than it earns.
iii.
Spending
a great deal of money to provide medical care for the aged is like wasting
money on a car. When a car is all worn out, needs a new engine, transmission,
and body work, it’s better just to junk it. The same goes for people.