Neotaoism: Sage-Nature | |
|
|
Introduction |
|
We recall
that the traditional understanding of Taoism was that things naturally
develop in a way that is their special way of developing, and that to try
to alter their development from the natural course is to make a great
mistake. Thus Zhuangzi said: The duck’s legs are short,
but if we try to lengthen them, the duck will feel pain. The crane’s legs
are long, but if we try to shorten them, the crane will feel grief.
Therefore we are not to amputate what is by nature long, nor to lengthen
what is by nature short.[1] And
amongst the things that deform our natural development are the rules of
human society. I think that moralities and
etiquette are inhuman. Just think how much distress the man who practises
them endures.[2] So
Zhuāngzǐ declares that it is proper not to follow these, just as did
Lǎozǐ. In stark
contrast, we saw that Confucian philosophers insisted upon the importance
of following the rules of propriety (li)
because these make it possible for people to have proper respectful
relationships with each other and for society to function smoothly. The
rules are important not so much in themselves but because acting according
to the rules teaches a certain set of dispositions and attitudes, and
those attitudes and dispositions are the virtues that the Confucians value
for their social effects. |
|
Living According To Nature
|
|
We
earlier saw that it was a fundamental claim of the classical Daoists that
it was right to live according to Nature. There are, however, several ways
in which the claim can be understood, and it is not clear that the
Classical Daoists properly distinguished these interpretations or resolved
the inconsistencies that resulted.
1.
Difficulties with the
Classical Interpretations The
classical Daoists had at least two understandings of such a basic
proposal: it might mean simply to act according to one’s natural
dispositions, or it might mean that there is a certain normative way of
behaving that is given by nature. That the second of these interpretations
was regarded as a reasonable position was seen when we discussed the claim
that
Turning back is how the Way moves. This text
was supposed to show that the ‘Dao’ that was observed to apply to the
non-human world could be taken as a guide to the actions of humans. It
assumes that if there is a rule that non-human things in the world
do follow, then that is a rule
that humans in the world should follow. This is not a leap that we would be inclined to make
these days. On the
other hand, the first interpretation is the one that supported the
radically antinomian approach of the classical Daoists which made Daoism
so incompatible with classic Confucianism. It was felt to be a reasonable
alternative interpretation (or perhaps it was never properly distinguished
from the second,) and it could be used to justify such outbursts as:
Exterminate the sage, discard the wise, These two
approaches are, of course, not obviously consistent. In fact, they are
pretty obviously contradictory. We have seen that the classical Daoists
seem to have been aware of the difficulty here, which led them to adopt a
somewhat obscurantist approach, and rather than accepting that two
inconsistent statements simply cannot be true together, they denied that
language could properly express their understandings. This is what lies
behind the famous claim that
The way that can be spoken of
2.
Recognising Impermanence The
injunction to ‘live according to Nature’ was also accepted by the
Neotaoists – it could hardly be otherwise, being so fundamental a part of
the Daoist teachings. The Neotaoists, however, identified in the classical
Daoist interpretation of that phrase an assumption or a presupposition
that there is a stable Nature according to which one may live. Such an
assumption in this place contrasted with the Daoist realisation elsewhere
that the world was full of change; indeed it was supposed to be a virtue
of the Daoist approach that it accepted the
necessity of change. The story,
shocking to Zhuangzi’s contemporaries, of that sage’s equanimity on the
occasion of his wife’s death was mentioned earlier to illustrate that
point. The
Neotaoists took the straightforward observation that things change and
made it central to their world view. Everything, they held, was in flux
and there is nothing permanent in the world. Change is all there is. One
natural consequence of this realisation is that there is a general problem
of identity in the world – including our own identity. So Guo Xiang could
write Thus Heaven, Earth, and all
things are ever in a state of change. The world is ever renewed, yet it
regards itself as old. A boat daily undergoes change, yet it seems to us
like the old one.[4]
A mountain daily undergoes change, yet it seems to us like the former one.
We touch the arm today and lose it. Everything imperceptibly passes away.
Therefore the ‘I’ of the past is no longer the ‘I’ of today. We must go
with what there is today, for how can we forever cling to what is past?[5] The institutions of the
former kings were intended to meet the needs of the time. If they are not
discarded after the time for them has passed, they become the bogy of the
people…[6]
[1]
Dàodéjīng
40
[2]
Dàodéjīng
19
[3]
Dàodéjīng
1
[4]
Compare with the ship
of Theseus.
[5]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary
3.12
[6]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary
(in Li Shu-ch’ang, ed. 1882-84,
Ku-yi Ts’ung-shu, Tokyo,
p. 68) (ref. in Fung Yu-lan, 1953,
HCP, Princeton U. P., v. 2,
p. 214.) |
|
The Sage |
|
In both
Daoism and Confucianism, we admire above all the person who instantiates
the philosophy as perfectly as possible and who thus becomes a ‘sage’ (圣,
shèng.) The Neotaoists were
likewise concerned to discover the characteristics and qualities of this
paragon and whether and how one might achieve such a status.
1.
The Sage Rejects Imitation The one
thing that we can already be sure of is that the true sage is not one who
imitates prior sages. Guo Xiang is very emphatic on this point, making at
least three arguments against imitation.
a.
It doesn’t match the current
situation For a
start, the true sage cannot be
one that does no more than imitate the actions of the past sages – and
this for the same reason that imitation of the sages is not a legitimate
guide for even non-sages. What those sages did was the result of their
sagely adaptation to the circumstances of their time, and those deeds
themselves are not necessarily appropriate to other times. One who behaves
in ways that are not appropriate to the time and place cannot be a sage.
b.
It won’t achieve sage-hood Moreover,
it is impossible for one to become
a sage through determined imitation, just as it is impossible for one to
become anything that is not already in one’s nature. A bird cannot aspire
to be a fish nor a stone to be a cloud. It is not possible to become a
great poet if one has not the talent for it, nor a fine artist likewise;
in trying to become a poet or a painter by initiating one, one will only
become an imitation of a poet or painter, and one’s own particular talents
(and we all do have special gifts) will remain undeveloped. Speaking of
several exemplary characters, Guō Xiang says The endowments of these men
were many-sided, for which they caused the whole world to leap to imitate
them. But imitation leads to a loss of individuality, and when
individuality is lost through
(imitation of)
something else, that something else becomes the creator of disorder.[1]
c.
It does harm to one’s nature But
perhaps the worst consequence of imitation is the damage that it does to
one’s own nature, for the effort to adopt the character of another must
have the effect of deforming one’s original character. Such a deformation
cannot be pursued – it is at the very least unnatural. The nature of everything has
its limit. If one is led on by what is beyond it, one’s nature will be
lost. One should disregard the inducement, and live according to oneself,
not according to others. In this way the integrity of one’s nature will be
preserved.[2]
2.
The Sage Rejects Knowledge
We can also be sure
that the sage does not become a sage because of any greater knowledge he
might have. The Neotaoists agreed with the Classical Daoists that
knowledge (by which was meant what we call ‘propositional knowledge’ or
‘knowledge that’) was not the way to the Dao. We have already seen that
Zhuangzi was sceptical about the possibility of such knowledge following
an argument similar to that of Descartes’s sceptical deconstruction of our
certainties. He was also dismissive of the possibility of such knowledge
being of any use in following
the Dao, preferring to emphasize the idea of practice, and the development
of one’s ‘knowledge how’ to follow the Dao.
The Neotaoists,
however, emphasized yet a third criticism. According to Guo Xiang again By knowledge we
mean [the
activity that attempts] what is
beyond [one’s natural ability]. That
which is within the sphere [of
one’s natural ability] is not
called knowledge. By being within the proper sphere we mean acting
according to one’s natural ability, attempting nothing that is beyond. If
carrying ten thousand ch’un is
in accordance with one’s ability, one will not feel the burden as weighty.
If discharging ten thousand functions [is
in accordance with one’s ability]
one will not feel the task as taxing.[3] Knowledge
of the kind that has been criticized is the sort of thing that requires an
effort to achieve. It is not a thing that comes to us naturally or as part
of our nature. Those who would follow their nature would not pursue
knowledge of that sort.
3.
The Sage Models
ziran Indeed,
the true sage acts only according to his own nature. He does not follow
‘institutions and morals’ (名教,
míng jiào:)
he enacts or instantiates or models
ziran (自然,)
literally ‘self-so’ or ‘self-so-ing,’ a Daoist concept which has many uses
but which is here used to signify ‘spontaneity’ or ‘naturalness.’ In
modelling naturalness the sage is also following the Dao, as Laozi
explains Humanity emulates earth,
A few observations
should be made here.
·
First, the text is not specific to sages but describes the situation in
general for Humanity or Human Nature. We
all model Nature and the Dao.
·
It is, moreover, ambiguous whether the claim is positive or normative: it
may be that each of the modellings is what is actually always happening,
but it may also be telling us that such modelling is how things ought to
be. We have seen this equivocation between the ‘is’ and the ‘ought’ of the
Dao before.
·
Furthermore, in this translation, as in many others,
ziran is translated as ‘Nature,’
but that may be somewhat misleading in this context. If instead we
translate it here as we do elsewhere as naturalness/spontaneity/self-so,
we get a different sense entirely.
·
And finally, Wang Bi pointed out that if the Way is empty or nothing,
then ziran is also nothing or
empty and so is Humanity. Human Nature may be said to model
ziran, but that is no more than to say that Human Nature (in its
original state) is ‘so-of-itself’ it is modelled upon nothing but is
sui generis. In such a state
Human Nature is compared to unshaped wood (朴,
pu)
To return now to
the question at hand, it is claimed that the sage is not required to make
any effort in order to follow the Dao because the sage is simply acting as
comes naturally. Recall that actions in accord with one’s nature are said
to be effortless, while actions against one’s nature require effort. The
Neotaoists insisted that in so doing, the sage could therefore be seen to
be following the principle of wu-wei,
because that principle, they asserted, only requires that one make no
effort and does not require that
one ‘do’ nothing. It is, however, very debatable whether this claim can be
squared with the plain words of Zz or Lz.
4.
The Sage Has Good
qi
As we remarked
above, it is clear that it is not only the sage whose nature emulates
ziran: it is all of humanity.
But all of humanity is not sage-like, and indeed, it was not always agreed
that sage-hood was available to all mankind. Moreover, the argument had
been made that it is ‘normal’ to behave naturally, and that that is what
would happen if anyone were released from the bonds of
‘institutions and morals.’ We
need to wonder, therefore, what it is about the (possible) sage that makes
his emulation of ziran a good
one and the rest of ours not so good.
One solution might
be that proposed by He Yan; that if we regard, as is normal, one’s nature
(性, xing) to be the product of
one’s qi-constitution, and we
accept, as is also normal, that variation in
qi- constitution is possible,
then in the nature of things certain people will have finer and richer
qi- constitution than others.
One’s capacities (才,
cai) and talents in all areas are also determined by this qi-
constitution. Therefore one could expect that those people with the very
finest and richest qi-
constitution will be such that their natures will be the most fine and
rich and their capacities and talents will be the best and that they will
best emulate the Dao. He Yan says that such a person may “merge
with the virtue of heaven and earth”[5]
Of course, if that
is the case then sages are born and not made. Indeed it would be
impossible to become a sage no matter how hard one tried
unless one already had the
appropriate qi; and
if one has the appropriate qi
then one is fortunate and one’s nature naturally models
ziran and Dao. This being
the case it is irrational to aspire to sage-hood unless one is already a
sage: it is not the sort of thing that is achievable for non-sages. One
might just as well aspire to be an attack helicopter. Rather, says He Yan,
we may set our sights upon achieving the status of a ‘worthy’ one (贤,
xián,)
such as Yan Hui, the ‘disciple’ of Confucius. The difference between the
two states is that Not even to have
the desire for the state of not desiring: this is the constant quality of
the sage. On the
other hand, Wang Bi insisted that the sage was like other men and not
different in kind, therefore each man could still aspire to being a sage.
This is presumably the case even if the
qi-constitution were the
determinative factor in the successful pursuit of sage-hood, because
no-one can know whether they have the necessary
qi-constitution except by the
results they achieve. In either case one’s qi-constitution doesn’t seem to
be a moral quality any more than one’s intelligence, health, height, or
physical fitness: it is simply part of one’s being that one has to accept
and work with.
5.
The Sage Masters Himself The
reason that ‘desire’ enters into the characterization above is that it was
believed that self-interested desire was an impediment to the proper
expression of ziran, because one’s actions would then be distorted by the desire
of things which were essentially
external to the self. Apart from that essential difficulty, it is also
the case that associating one’s contentment with external things which are
outside one’s control – and the effort to control those external things –
is always liable to failure and will lead to unhappiness. (This is an
attitude which we might also recognise from the Epicureans and the
Buddhists.) It is much better and safer to make the necessities of one’s
life only those things that are within oneself and within one’s control. Some
thought that desires themselves were therefore unnatural and required to
be annihilated, but others thought that they were a natural product of the
mind and could only be regulated. It was generally agreed, however, that
there was a distinction to be made between the desires for necessary
things like food and water and the desires for unnecessary things like
power and wealth. The former were essentially limited while the latter
were unlimited and so the former were much less likely to be damaging to
the sage-aspirant than the latter. The
mastery of desires was, however, only one part of a more general mastery
that the sage was expected to assert over his inner life. The more extreme
positon – championed by He Yan, for example – held that the sage did not
have emotions (无情,
wu qíng) because the sage was
complete and self-sufficient and lacked nothing.[7]
Wang Bi, on the other hand, allowed that sages did have emotions but that
they were not enthralled by them. He could recommend that emotions be
subordinated to reason, as in the case of Meng-sun Ts’ai’s equanimity at
the funeral of his mother as reported by Zhuangzi.[8]
6.
The Sage Makes No Distinctions One of
the tools of reason which could aid the sage-aspirant in the control of
his emotions was the belief that there was no justification for becoming
specially attached to anything in the world, because there was no such
thing as a difference between things in the world. If there are no
differences and everything is just the same, then how can we distinguish
any one thing as worthy of our special regard or rejection? We looked at
the kinds of arguments used to support this point of view in the lectures
on The School of Names and on Zhuangzi’s Skepticism. The arguments of Hui
Shi of the School of Names were comprehensible as demonstrations that some
statements may be true from one point of view and false from another point
of view, which suggests that he was arguing, at least partially, for a
kind of relativism in propositional knowledge. We can see that Zhuangzi,
who was a friend of Hui Shi, made arguments to the same effect for
functional knowledge. The most
important of these relativistic claims was that there was no difference
between good and bad, which is always a popular doctrine with a certain
type of person. Perhaps feeling that it needed more support than its being
a logical consequence of a more general claim of universal
indistinguishability, Guo Xiang offered the unfortunately familiar
argument that If the right is really
absolutely right, in the world there should be none that considers it to
be wrong. If the wrong is really absolutely wrong there should be none
that considers it to be right. The fact that there are uncertainty between
right and wrong, and a confusion in distinctions, shows that the
distinctions between right and wrong are due to a partiality of view, and
that all things are really in agreement.[9]
[1]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary
4.29
[2]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary
10
[3]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary
3
[4]
DDJ 25 (Cleary’s tr.)
[5]
Commentary on
Lun Yu,
14.35 and 16.8
[6]
GX, Chuang-tzu Commentary,
‘Introduction’ (quoting a philosopher of the 5th C)
[7]
HY,
Sanguozhi 28,
commentary
[8]
Zz 6.75ff
[9]
[9] GX,
Chuang-tzu Commentary,
c. 2 |
|