The School of Yin and Yang | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Introduction |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The early Chinese philosophers were almost entirely concerned with
questions of ethics and behaviour, and we have seen that where some began
to take an interest in other fields – even where they were apparently
motivated by a desire to better pursue ethical questions – their efforts
were largely unappreciated. The School of Names, for example, disappeared
unlamented by its contemporaries and remembered to posterity only as a
congeries of worthless quibblers. This is very different from the Greek
experience, where philosophy began as a cosmological enquiry into the
basic structure and constituency of the universe; questioning whether it
was made of one material or many, whether the substance was of some
familiar kind or something else, whether there was change in that material
or not, and so on. These questions were little considered by most of the
philosophers whose reputations have endured, and then usually just to say
that that was not their business, but there were some who thought these
matters worth attention.
The same Han dynasty historians (Sima Tan, quoted in the
Shiji or
Records of the Grand Historian written by his son Sima Qian) who
invented a ‘School of Names’ to include all those interested in language,
analysis, skepticism, relativism, logic, etc. also invented the ‘School of
Yin and Yang’ ( 阴阳家, Yīnyángjiā)
to neatly contain those who were concerned with cosmological
questions. (We shall call them the ‘Yinyangists’ from now on.) The name
refers to the famous complementary or oppositional pair in terms of which
much of their explanation was phrased, but these philosophers, if that’s
what we wish to call them, also made use of the so-called ‘Five Elements,’
and of course all this was related to the influence of
qi. All of these seem to have
been part of the early Chinese pre-philosophical background: the effect of
the speculations of the Yinyangists was to regularise the popular notions
and to rationalise them to a certain degree.
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Correlative Cosmology
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The point of a cosmology is not only to describe how the world is
constituted but also to explain
how it operates. Without going into too much detail about what qualifies
as an explanation – because this is an increasingly controversial area of
philosophy – I think it’s reasonable to say that we now think of
explanations – in the cosmological realm, at least – as being essentially
causal: we say that we have explained why X happened or why X is the way
it is when we have shown how the pre-existing conditions
cause X to be the way it is or
they cause X to come about. For
example, we say that the apple falls to the ground because the Force of
Gravity existing between two masses causes them to move towards each
other; or we say that the sky is blue because the shorter wavelengths of
light (at the blue end of the spectrum) are scattered into our eyes by
particles in the atmosphere while the longer ones pass through unaffected.
These aren’t the only sorts of explanations, however. Another way of
thinking of explanations is as being any appropriate way of answering a
‘why is it so?’ question: and whether some way of answering is appropriate
or not depends on what we want to do with that answer. In the West,
philosophers were for a long time convinced by Aristotle’s ‘Four Causes’
categorization of explanations according to which there were just four
different ways of answering one of those questions. We could say there was
a material cause: the statue is brown because the statue is made of bronze
and bronze is brown. Or a formal cause: the man is unmarried because he is
a bachelor, and a bachelor is an unmarried man. Or an efficient cause: the
child is ugly because both parents are ugly and ugly parents tend to have
ugly children. (This is Aristotle’s example!
and this is the only one of his
explanation types that we think of as causal in the our sense.) Or,
finally, a final cause: the statue was made to be placed in the temple.
Now, despite Aristotle’s claim that he has enumerated all the possible
kinds of reply to the ‘why?’ question, we shall see that the cosmology of
the Yinyangists accepts a sort of answer that does not occur in his list:
a type of answer that we now
find very difficult to accept as any sort of answer at all – let alone as
an answer suitable for the cosmological domain. For the Yinyangists an
appropriate explanation for some phenomenon is to simply find a place for
that phenomenon in a scheme of correlated categorizations. This was
justified by such considerations as the following from the 3rd
C BC Lüshi chunqiu:[1]
Things
of the same kind summon each other, those with the same vital energy join
together, and sounds that match resonate. Thus if you strum a gong note
other gong will resonate; if you strum a jue note other jue will
vibrate. Use a dragon to bring rain; use the form to move the shadow. The
masses of people think that fortune and misfortune come from fate [ming].
How could they know from where they truly come! This is not particularly a Chinese ‘Way of Thought.’ Similar modes of reasoning were used throughout the pre-modern world from Mesoamerica to India. In particular, we know perfectly well that the same sort of theorizing was at one time common in the West – again, despite the explicit acceptance of Aristotle’s categorization of explanations. In fact, this sort of thing continued well into the modern period as we can see with Kepler’s attempt to ‘explain’ the relative distances of the planets from the Sun by ‘correlating’ them with the Platonic perfect solids.[2] According to that scheme, the reason that Venus is as far from the Sun as it is is because the icosahedron is related in such and such a way to the octahedron and dodecahedron. It is one of the triumphs of modernity that such things are now inconceivable to us as explanations, but a sympathetic understanding of pre-modern thought requires that we accept that it was not always so.
[1]
Chen Qiyou (1984)
Lüshi Chunqiu Xinshi,
Shanghai: Shanghai Guji Chubanshe;
20/4: 1369
[2]
Kepler, J. (1596) Mysterium
Cosmographicum |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Yin and Yang |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
[In
the same way] there are six heavenly influences (qi,)
which descend and produce the five tastes, go forth in the five colours,
and are verified in the five notes; but when they are in excess, they
produce the six diseases. Those 6 influences are denominated by the
yin, the yang, wind, rain,
obscurity, and brightness.[1] At this point then, qi is not a
unitary element pervading and guiding the universe, but a general term for
a species of influences (plural.) These six
qi are also mentioned in an
inner chapter.of the Zhuangzi.[2]
Moreover, yin and
yang at this time are not the
universal classifiers of all phenomena, but just two particular kinds of
phenomena – apparently, the shady side of the hill (north,) and the sunny
side (south.) The relevant characters appearing on oracle bones of the
Shang dynasty (1556-1046 BC) seem to refer to weather conditions such as
sunniness and darkness.
At some indeterminate time this pair began to become dominant over the
other six qi. In Zz 22.11, which
is possibly 3rd-2nd C BC, we read that
We use
the expression Sky and Earth to express hugeness of shape; we use
yin and
yang for greatness of the
breaths (qi)
And this led naturally enough to the idea that
qi is one thing and that yin
and yang are the two forms which
it takes, or the two ways in which it acts. In that view
qi might be taken as responsible for everything according to the
actions of the qi. Thus in Zz
22.11 it is said that
When
heaven and earth were formed, they divided into yin and yang. Yang is
generated from yin and yin is
generated from yang. Yin and yang mutually alternate
which makes four fields penetrate. Sometimes there is life, sometimes
there is death, that brings the myriad things to completion.[3]
And in fact we find that that text then goes on to give a very long and
involved cosmogony in which the creation of the world and everything in it
is described as having been produced by the separation of opposites all
related to the actions or characters of the
yin and
yang aspects of the unitary
qi. One short passage will give
you the flavour of the whole:
The
Way of Heaven is to be round, the way of Earth is to be square. It is
primary to the square to be dim, primary to the round to shine. To shine
is to expel qi, for which reason fire and sun cast the image outside. To be dim
is to hold qi in, for which
reason water and the moon draw the image inside. What expels
qi does to, what holds
qi in is transformed
by. Therefore the
yang does to, the
yin is transformed
by.[4]
From this point on the Chinese predilection for pairwise oppositions
becomes intimately associated with the
yin-yang division: they are
taken as the model – if not the cause – of all such divisions, and lists
of such correlations become pervasive in the cosmological literature. The
earliest reasonably complete such list is from a recently discovered text
of the Laozi discovered at
Mawangdui dating to about 250BC. In which we find these associations:[5]
You will recall that we said that the Yinyangists developed from the
class of occult practitioners of earlier times and that amongst their
skills was divination. Since the Yinyangists, or some of them anyway, now
believed that the world was directed by the actions of
yin and
yang, it is not surprising that
they thought that the method of divination needed to be related in some
correspondential way to the yin
and yang.
The classic form of divination in the Shang period was by oracle bones,
but in this new age the preferred method was by casting yarrow stalks.
Somehow the stalks were made to yield 6 numbers each between 6 and 9. Each
even number would be coded as a broken line and each odd number as a solid
one. This would yield a hexagram consisting of 6 broken or unbroken lines
(corresponding to a number between 0 and 63) and each hexagram would then
be interpreted by looking up the corresponding text in a book where they
were listed with their associated symbolic meanings.[6]
The original book for this purpose was a divination text in use in the
Western Zhou called the Zhōuyì (周易)
or the ‘Changes of Zhou.’
With the addition of ten commentaries known as the ‘Wings,’ which relate
the diagrams to cosmology and which mostly date to about 200 BC, this
became the text that we know today as the Yìjīng
(易经) or ‘Classic of
Changes.’
It was the binary fact of the broken and unbroken lines of the hexagrams
that suggested a connection to yin
and yang. It was natural to
connect yang to the unbroken
line and yin to the broken one,
and the piling up of the choices of
yin and yang in constructing
the hexagrams then mirrored the process of creation of all things as we
saw it described above in the
Huainanzi.
[1]
Legge, J. (1893)
The Ch’un Tsew
with the Tso Chuen,
2 ed. (London: Oxford UP) p. 580 f.
[2]
Zz 1.21
[3]
Liu An (ed.) (1998) Huainanzi, Xi’an: Sanqing Press, c. 2
[4]
Hnz 3. Tr. in Graham,
A. C. (1989) Disputers of
the Tao Chicago IL: Open Court, p. 332
[5]
Graham,
op. cit.. pp.330f
[6]
The historical
relationship between these hexagrams and the eight trigrams, the
bagua (八卦,)
is unknown |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Five Elements |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
We find a possible early mention of the five elements in the
Zuo Zhuan where it is said that:
Heaven
and earth have their regular ways, and men like these for their pattern,
imitating the brilliant bodies of Heaven, and according with the natural
diversities of the Earth. (Heaven and Earth) produce the six atmospheric
conditions (qi,) and make use of the five material elements.[1]
That mention is a little obscure however, and the first definite
reference to the elements as a cosmological pattern occurs in the
Shu Jing (the ‘Classic of
History’ which is now supposed to have been written some time before the 4th
C BC,) in a section called the Hóng Fàn
or ‘Great Plan,’ which included:
First,
the five elements: the first is water; the second, fire; the third, wood;
the fourth, metal; and the fifth, earth. The nature of water is to soak
and descend; of fire to blaze and ascend; of wood to be crooked and
straight; of metal to yield and change; while that of earth is seen in
seed-sowing and in-gathering.[2]
Now, the term ‘element’ translating
xing here is misleading, because the character usually means something
like ‘going.’ When the specifically material nature of those elements is
to be emphasized the word cai (材,
‘materials’) could be used, as it is in a reference to the five materials
in the Zuo zhuan.[3]
Here, then, it seems more likely that the list of
xing should be understood not as naming the constitutive elements of
the material world, but as standing for the different natures which are
associated with those things. Alternative translations for
xing have been offered such as ‘phase’, ‘process,’ etc., but I think
‘nature’ would do just as well. Nevertheless, to respect tradition, we
shall stick with ‘element.’
It was noted quite early that the five elements could be put into two
cycles. One cycle would show how each element overcame another other.
Parts at least of this cycle were known to the authors of the
Zuo zhuan. For example, at one point a person, Ying, wanted to know
whether he should go to war against the House of Keang and was told “Ying
is a name of water …. The emperor Yen had his fire-master from whom the
House of Keang is descended. Water overcomes fire. According to this you
may attack the Keang.”[4]
The full destructive (克,
kè)
cycle
was: Water extinguishes Fire melts Metal cuts Wood digs Soil dams Water
Another cycle would show that each element gave rise to the other. The
generative (生,
shēng)
cycle
was:
Water feeds Wood fuels Fire produces Earth brings forth
Metal collects Water
Many other interrelationships could also be found between the various
elements. When correlated with other 5-fold categorizations these
interrelationships were supposed to carry over to the new categorization
so that knowing how the five elements related would immediately reveal the
hidden relationships of the newly correlated phenomena. Such five-fold
correlations began to appear with the
Spring and Autumn Annals of Master Lü
(Lüshi Chunqiu)
in about 239 BC. Lists of such five-fold categorizations and their
correlations with the five elements then became as tediously widespread as
the pairwise correlations of the
Yin-yang theorists. To illustrate the type, we shall give just one
early list drawn from the
Lüshi Chunqiu[5]
in a section that was eventually canonised by inclusion in the
Liji
(礼记,
‘Book of Rites’) as the chapter ‘Monthly Commands’ (月令,
Yuèlìng.)
It is obvious even in this early effort that a five-fold division is
considerably less flexible than a pairwise one. It signally fails to do
justice to things which are naturally four-fold, such as the seasons and
the directions. In the case of the seasons the problem was occasionally
solved by inserting a notional intermediate period in the calendar, but
this is hardly satisfactory. It is also much less intuitively obvious how
to make the associations. In the case for the
yin-yang categories, once we see
one or two such assignments we have a pretty good idea where the rest are
going to go. That is certainly not the case for the
wu xing: how are the notes
supposed to be distributed according to the elements, for example?
Justifications for most of the
associations are very strained. And it’s also doubtful in many cases that
most of the supposed correlative relationships can be plausibly defended.
How does the cycle of generation work for the creatures in the list above,
for example?
Notwithstanding the difficulties attaching to such correspondences, it
was from very early proposed that there were aspects of human life that
could usefully be put into such relationships. The ‘Monthly Commands’ just
mentioned, set out the proper behaviour month by month for the ruler and
the kingdom to be in harmony with Nature, together with warnings of the
dire consequences that will ensue if disharmony arises.
In the
first month of spring the East wind resolves the cold. Creatures that have
been torpid during the winter begin to move … It is in this month that the
vapours of Heaven descend and those of Earth ascend. Heaven and Earth are
in harmonious cooperation.
…
He
charges his assistants to disseminate virtue and harmonious governmental
order, so as to give effect to the expression of his satisfaction … In
this month no warlike operations should be undertaken; the undertaking of
such is sure to be followed by calamities from Heaven.[6]
This early stage of theorising about
wu xing culminated with the work
of Zou Yan (鄒衍,
305–240 BC,)
a scholar of the Jixia Academy of Qi who began the effort to combine the
teachings of wu xing with those
of yin yang. He is said to have
written copiously – a book of 00,000 characters – but none of that has
survived and we have only the remains of quoted passages, some comments by
others, and a brief biographical notice in Sima Qian’s
Shiji. He is most famous for his
geographical studies and for an attempt at a philosophy of history. That
philosophy is described in the
Lüshi Chunqiu.[7]
It suggests that the dynasties receiving the Mandate of Heaven are those
who are associated with the power of the currently ascendant element,
which is knowable by correctly reading the omens, and that dynasties rise
and fall according to the succession of elements in the destructive cycle.
Thus:
In the
time of Yu [founder of the Hsia dynasty] Heaven first made grass and trees
appear which did not die in the autumnand winter. Yu said: ;The force of
Wood is in ascendancy.” Therefore he assumed green as his colour and took
Wood as the pattern for his affairs.
In the
time of T’ang [founder of the Shang dynasty] Heaven made some knife blades
appear in the water. T’ang said: “The force of Metal is in ascendancy.” He
therefore assumed white as his colour and took Metal as the pattern for
his affairs.
[1]
Legge, J. (1893)
The Ch’un Tsew
with the Tso Chuen,
2 ed. (London: Oxford UP) p. 708
[2]
Waltham, C. (1972)
Shu Ching, London:
George Allen and Unwin, p. 126 (pt 5 c. 4)
[3]
Legge
op. cit.
p. 534 (tr.)
[4]
Legge
op. cit.
p. 819
[5]
Graham,
op. cit.. pp.341
[6]
Fung Yu-lan (1948) A Short
History of Chinese Philosophy NY: Macmillan, p. 134
[7]
XIII, 2 |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Conclusion |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
These cosmological theories were never really accepted by the philosophers, who mostly simply ignored them. At best they got the occasional mention by someone like Zhuangzi (as we’ve seen.) At worst they were severely attacked by others such as Xunzi. Nevertheless, the theories continued to flourish into the Han dynasty and later for several reasons. In the first place their theories promised to be useful to the rulers of states in being able to provide more immediately applicable advice than they were likely to get from the other philosophers, and the barbaric Qin emperor so far favoured them that their texts were not proscribed and destroyed, which must also have provided an advantage in propagating their messages. But perhaps the most important reason for their flourishing is that they did at least provide some sort of cosmology. After a certain level of sophistication in society it is hard to live with a fractured and gappy world view. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||