Zhuangzi | |
|
|
Introduction |
|
That
book, also known as the Zhuangzi,
is not only an essential philosophical text but also one of the great
literary productions of China and really a very entertaining read. (It was
officially recognised as a Classic by the Emperor in 742.) Its literary
quality is all the more remarkable in that it has long been recognised
that the book is actually a compilation of pieces by many hands rather
than the work of a single author. Presumably, we can give significant
credit for this to one
Guō
Xiàng (郭象,
d. 312,) an editor and commentator of genius who removed large amounts of
what he judged to be repetitive, extraneous, and unworthy material from
the ancient original resulting in the book of 33 chapters that we now
have. Nevertheless, it
is thought that only the first seven of these chapters, known as the
‘Inner’ chapters, are likely to be the work of Zhuang Zhou.
The ‘Outer’ chapters (8-22) may be by disciples of the master; and the
‘Miscellaneous’ chapters (23-33)
by members of the ‘school’ of Zhuangzi. (Modern scholars claim to have
seen other divisions in there too, but that needn’t concern us here.) In the
text of the Zhuangzi our
philosopher challenges his contemporaries and criticizes the teachings and
methods of the Confucians, Mohists, and others, giving us a fund of
contemporary information on those movements. In particular, as the
relevant lecture made clear, a great deal of what we know of the ‘School
of Names’ comes from the appearance in the
Zhuangzi of philosophers of that
school such as Hui Shi and Gongsun Long as targets of Zhuangzi’s
criticism. Zhuangzi clearly found the claims of the ‘School of Names’
significant – even if he didn’t properly engage with them. It is even said
that he was a friend of Hui Shi himself and considered him his
philosophical peer and a valuable interlocutor.
|
|
Exploring the Limits |
|
Relativism Many of
the theses that his friend Hui Shi proposed seem to be comprehensible as
demonstrations that some statements may be true from one point of view and
false from another point of view, which suggests that he was arguing, at
least partially, for a kind of relativism in propositional knowledge. We
can see that Zhuangzi made arguments to the same effect for functional
knowledge. A couple of passages will serve for the innumerable others Now I would ask you this, If
a man sleeps in a damp place, he gets lumbago and dies. But how about an
eel? And living up in a tree is precarious and trying to the nerves. But
how about monkeys? Of the man, the eel, and the monkey, whose habitat is
the right one, absolutely? Human beings feed on flesh, deer on grass,
centipedes on little snakes, owls and crows on mice. Of these four, whose
is the right taste, absolutely? Monkey mates with the dog-headed female
ape, the buck with the doe, eels consort with fishes, while men admire Mao
Ch'iang and Li Chi, at the sight of whom fishes plunge deep down in the
water, birds soar high in the air, and deer hurry away. Yet who shall say
which is the correct standard of beauty? In my opinion, the doctrines of
humanity and justice and the paths of right and wrong are so confused that
it is impossible to know their contentions.[1] Formerly a
sea-bird alighted in the suburban country of Lu. The marquis went out to
meet it, (brought it) to the ancestral temple, and prepared to banquet it
there. The Kiu-shâo was performed to afford it music; an ox, a sheep, and
a pig were killed to supply the food. The bird, however, looked at
everything with dim eyes, and was very sad. It did not venture to eat a
single bit of flesh, nor to drink a single cupful; and in three days it
died. Clearly,
there is no proper way that is not proper
with respect to the person or
thing involved. On the other hand, as you may have noticed from the
examples, it doesn’t follow that we can’t know what the proper way is with
respect to that thing. Clearly, we’re meant to understand that it is
proper for eels to sleep in damp places, monkeys to sleep in trees, and
men to sleep in soft beds. By the same token he describes, with no show of
hesitation, just how one who knew the ways of birds would treat one
properly.
Skepticism But what
sort of knowledge is it that we have when we know the proper ways of eels
and monkeys, birds and men? One strand of Zhuangzi’s writing strongly
suggests that he doesn’t think that such knowledge is itself propositional
knowledge, because there is a doubt that propositional knowledge is even
possible. We are
familiar, I suppose, with the general arguments for skepticism about
propositional knowledge in the Western tradition, if only from our
memories of the Cartesian argument. There are traces of something like
that same skeptical procedure in the
Zhuangzi, with the notable exception of the very first step in which
we are urged to doubt the veracity of our own senses. It cannot have
escaped the notice of thinkers at any time that we may be mistaken about
the things we believe we see or hear, and yet there is no good evidence
that this was felt to be an important epistemological limit by Chinese
philosophers before the introduction of Buddhism in the 1st C
AD.[3]
1.
The Problem of Dreams
Descartes’s second step was to question whether he could distinguish
between the fantasies that come as dreams and the experiences that come in
waking life: How often, in the still of
the night, I have the familiar conviction that I am here, wearing a cloak,
sitting by the fire – when really I am undressed and lying in bed! … When
I think more clearly about this, I see so plainly that sleep and waking
can never be distinguished by any certain signs, that I am bewildered …[4] And
Zhuangzi made precisely the same point, though more picturesquely: I, Chuang Chou, once dreamed
that I was a butterfly flitting about. I did whatever I wanted! I knew
nothing about any Chuang Chou. Then I suddenly awakened as Chuang Chou
with all his normal trappings. Now I don’t know whether Chuang Chou
dreamed he was a butterfly or a butterfly is dreaming that he is Chuang
Chou.[5]
2.
The Problem of Reason Descartes
recognised, however, that even if we couldn’t be sure that we were not
dreaming, still there were things that were true even so. Things like red
being a colour, bodies having extension, and so on. Similarly, St
Augustine at this point in his own treatment of skepticism declared that
we could still not doubt that logical truths were true or that
mathematical or geometrical truths still held.[6]
The Third
Cartesian step was to introduce the possibility of a deceptive Demon whose
power was such that it could force us to make errors even in acknowledging
those facts. If you wonder how that is possible you need to simply ask
yourself how it is that you are
certain that 1 + 1 = 2: it isn’t by repeated experience of that being
the case, because we just don’t think that we get mathematical or logical
truths by extrapolating from experience. (If we did, we’d have to find it
conceivable that some experience could tell us that 1 + 1 =
something other than 2; and we don’t. If no experience can contradict it
then it wasn’t experience that told us it was true.) Apparently we just
have an intuition of the truth of such matters, and an intuition, being a
subjective phenomenon, has no independent guarantee of truth. Zhuangzi
has nothing like the Demon, but he does have an argument that makes the
related suggestion that our intuitions about rationality are less than
infallible. Suppose that you and I
debated and you bested me, would it mean that you were naturally right and
I was naturally wrong? Or even vice versa? Or would one be partially right
and the other partially wrong? Or would both be both right and wrong? And
if you and I cannot come to a mutual understanding, others assuredly will
experience the same difficulty, so who can we get to set things straight?
Anybody agreeing with me will only repeat my own arguments, and we shall
still be in the dark. Somebody differing with both of us merely offers
another point of view, and somebody agreeing with both of us brings us
back to the starting point. So, if neither you nor I nor another man can
come to a mutual understanding, shall we await a fourth?[7] And if we cannot rely upon the results of reasoned argument any more than we can rely upon our experience of the world (which may be just a dream,) then it must seem that there is no way to be sure of how things are.
[1]
Zz 2.65 ff
[2]
Zz 18.30 ff
[3]
Graham, A. C. (1989)
Disputers of the Tao,
Open Court, p. 84
[4]
Descartes, R.
Meditations I (Anscombe
& Geach (1954) Descartes:
Philosophical Writings, London: Thomas Nelson, p. 62)
[5]
Zz 2.95
[6]
Augustine, Against the Academicians, 3.10.23
[7]
Zz 2.85 ff
|
|
Knowing the Dao |
|
The way that can be spoken of
1.
Practice makes Perfect The
Dào is to be discovered only by
long practical experience and never by knowing any doctrines. One can no
more learn the Dào by learning
doctrines than one can learn to ride a bike by reading about how to ride a
bike. Consider the butcher Ding. [He]
was cutting up an ox for the ruler Wän-hui. Whenever he applied his hand,
leaned forward with his shoulder, planted his foot, and employed the
pressure of his knee, in the audible ripping off of the skin, and slicing
operation of the knife, the sounds were all in regular cadence. Movements
and sounds proceeded as in the dance of 'the Mulberry Forest' and the
blended notes of 'the King Shâu.' And the
wheelwright Bian also pointed out the inutility of verbal instruction.
Duke Hwan, seated
above in his hall, was (once) reading a book, and the wheelwright Phien
was making a wheel below it. Laying aside his hammer and chisel, Phien
went up the steps, and said,
2.
Practice, But To What End? There is,
however, a problem with the idea that the perfection of ones knowledge of
the Dào is like the perfection
of ones knowledge of wheelwrighting or of butchery. When one practices
cutting up oxen there is always a final goal at which one aims and which
one can use as a guiding principle: are the cuts of meat produced
correctly cut for the kitchen or not. Similarly with the crafting of a
wheel; the guiding criterion by which one may judge the correctness of the
performance is the utility of the wheel produced. By comparing the results
of ones performance of the task at hand against the appropriate criteria
one learns whether the performance is adequate to the task or not and thus
comes to learn how to do it properly. But what can play the role of such a
criterion for the Dào? The
answer is that there is no such criterion. Suppose that we propose X as
the criterion. To take that criterion as a guide to action is to say that
the statement ‘X should be our guide’ is true. The Mohist, for example,
proposes to take the criterion of success in actions to be ‘the greatest
benefit’ and accordingly says that it is true that ‘the greatest benefit
should be our guide.’ But we’ve just seen that Zhuangzi does not think
that we can know the truth of any proposition (because propositional
knowledge is not to be had,) and therefore we cannot know that the
criterion X – whatever it may be – is a proper guide to action. But
without a sound criterion of judgement how can we come to know the
Dào? All that
is left to the seeker after the Dào
is to act spontaneously, without reference to a guiding principle – and
even this cannot be taken as a principle. The situation is rather like
that of the Skeptics (Pyrrhonists) of ancient Greece who could not say
that they knew nothing, because that would itself be a claim to knowledge,
but only that they would withhold judgement. Those who would follow
Zhuangzi could only deny that any principle of action was the way to the
Dào. All that is possbible is to
provide the image of the sage in action:
Within yourself, no fixed positions
|
|