Xunzi | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Introduction
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The Mencian claim that human nature is good
eventually became the accepted position in Confucianism, but for over
twelve hundred years the question was disputed with the followers of Xunzi
(荀子)
who argued the opposite: that human nature was essentially bad. Xunzi,
whose name was actually
Xún Kuŕng
(荀況,) is yet another of those early characters whose
histories are not very well known – but at least we can be sure of his
having existed. His dates are probably something like 310 BC- 220 BC. In
Sima Qian’s ‘Records of the Historian’ (c. 74) he is said to have been
born in the state of Zhao, and to have gone at the age of fifty (or 15) to
join the Ji Xia Academy in the state of Qi, a briefly brilliant
institution which attracted many of the philosophers of the Hundred
Schools during the Warring States Period, and which we might compare for
its influence to the Library of Alexandria in Egypt or to the Nalanda
Mahavihara in India. He is supposed to have had as students both Han Fei,
whom we have met as the great theorist of the Legalist school, and Li Si,
who as Grand Poo Bah under the first emperor shaped many of the enduring
imperial institutions (and also recommended burning books and burying
scholars.) According to the histories, after his time at that school Xunzi
became the usual wandering scholar seeking position. Eventually, he was
employed as a minister in Lanling. When his patron there was assassinated
he retired but remained in that state until his death.
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Heaven, Earth, and Man |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
A notable character of this philosophical system
is its determined secularism. Xunzi does not deny Heaven or the
Dao, but he never considers them as supernatural parts of the
universe and he never appeals to supernatural forces in order to
explain something that needs explaining. Concerning Heaven, he
says that[1] Heaven operates with constant regularity. It does not prevail because of
[the sage king] Yao; nor
does it cease to prevail because of [the tyrant]
Jie. Respond to it with good government, and blessings will
result; respond to it with misgovernment, and misfortune will
result.
As a consequence of this view, of course, two
things follow immediately. Firstly, whatever the causes of various
unusual events might be, they are certainly not portents of doom
or signs that Heaven is trying to communicate with Man. When stars fall or the sacred trees groan, all the people become afraid
and ask: “What is the significance of all this?” I would say:
There is no special significance. This is just due to a
modification of Heaven and earth and the mutation of yin and yang.
These are rare phenomena. We may marvel at them, but we should not
fear them.
And secondly, whatever might be the point of
prayers and imprecations to Heaven, the one thing they will not do
is alter the action of Heaven. If people pray for rain and it rains, how is that? I would say: Nothing in
particular. Just as when people do not pray for rain, it also
rains.
It was Xunzi’s opinion that the three powers of
the world – that is: Heaven, Earth, and Man – had each their own
Way or dao, by which he
meant a norm of operation. That is to say, there was a distinct
way that each of them was supposed to act and those ways were
largely independent of each other: nothing good would come from
confusing them. Heaven has its seasons; earth has its resources; man has his government.
This is how man is able to form a triad with Heaven and earth. If
man should neglect his own part in this triad and put all his hope
in Heaven and earth with which he forms the triad, he is making a
grave mistake.
The proper nature of Man’s relationship with the
other two powers is one of beneficent exploitation. No doubt, the
intention would be that the proper role of each power was to
provide the grounds for benefits to the other two, but Xunzi only
felt the need to insist upon the propriety of getting benefits
from Heaven and earth. You exalt Heaven and meditate on it: why not domesticate it and regulate
it? ... … If the Way is followed and not deviated from, then Heaven cannot send
misfortune. Under such circumstances, flood or drought cannot
cause a famine, extreme cold or heat cannot cause any malady, and
unusual apparitions cannot cause disaster.
[1]
Xz c. 17
(‘Discourse on Heaven’)
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Human Nature
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The dao
of Man is thus the way of being or behaving that is optimal for Man
regarding his relations with Heaven and Earth. Xunzi believed as a good
Confucian that the dao for Man
was that proposed by Confucius. However, it is clear whereas Heaven and
Earth invariably follow their dao
because that is their nature, it is equally clear that humans do not have
the same advantage and that they may follow or not follow the
dao that is set for them. Therefore we can say that their nature is
at least not determinative of their following their
dao. In this Mencius and Xunzi would doubtless agree, and the
difference between them is just that Mencius believed that human nature
is, nevertheless, naturally disposed to discover the true
dao, whereas Xunzi thought that the true
dao was not a natural disposition of human nature.
Xunzi’s arguments are well set out in chapter 23
of the Xunzi, rather bluntly
titled ‘Human Nature is Detestable’ (xěng č, 性恶.) There are several, but the fundamental argument is
from simple observation. We can see in others, as we recognise in
ourselves, that what is natural to man is that he values his self-interest
and, all things being equal, will pursue it. Moreover, the effect of this
pursuit is to set every man against his neighbour and to make life most
unpleasant for everyone.
Now people’s nature is such that they are born with a fondness for profit
in them. If they follow along with this, then struggle and contention will
arise, and yielding and deference will perish therein.
You may recognise this as being quite similar to
Hobbes’s view of the State of Nature that existed (hypothetically) before
any sovereign ruled and each man was guided by his own prudential reason.
In that case the result was a life ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and
short.’ For Hobbes, the desire to exit the State of Nature was the
justification for submission to the sovereign as the necessary condition
of escape; and similarly for Xunzi, the escape from this bad condition
required the acceptance of external moral codes.
It is necessary to await the transforming influence of teachers and models
and the guidance of ritual and
yi [righteousness,] and only then
will they come to yielding and deference, turn to proper form and order,
and end up becoming controlled.
It’s worth noticing at this point that both
Mencius and Xunzi believed that men naturally
prefer the good – if it is possible to achieve it – and both believe
that man is uniquely capable of achieving it, so it might not be
absolutely clear where they are in fundamental disagreement. Essentially
the controversy comes down to a disagreement over what it means for some
characteristic to be something’s ‘nature’ (a controversy which is not
unknown also in Western philosophy.) Mencius thought that what constituted
the ‘nature’ of a thing was what it was uniquely
capable of doing; so the nature
of Man was good, because Man uniquely possessed the four seeds of goodness
that could be developed into the
appropriate virtues. Xunzi thought that the nature of a member of some
class was just what was universally true of all members of that class; so
the nature of Man was bad because it was a universal truth that Man was
guided by the love of profit, which was a tendency that was socially
destructive when left uncorrected. From a distance, it might seem that the
debate was a case of two schools talking past each other rather than to
each other: ignoring the summary judgement on ‘human nature,’ there seems
no reason why one would feel forced to choose between their positions. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
a.
Its Purpose
1.
The Coordination of Interests
One obvious reason for the introduction of ritual
was for the coordination of interests in society. This coordination has
two parts. In the first place ritual was instituted in order to regulate
the behaviour of people and to put limits on their perfectly rational
actions to satisfy their selfish desires.
Humans are born having desires. When they have desires but do not get the
objects of their desire, then they cannot but seek some means of
satisfaction. If there is no measure or limit to their seeking, then they
cannot help but struggle with each other. If they struggle with each other
there will be chaos, and if there is chaos they will be impoverished.[1]
This, again, is reminiscent of an argument made by
Hobbes, who identified competition as one of the three sources of
contention in the State of Nature.[2] It is usual now when discussing
this problem in Hobbes to refer to the Prisoner’s Dilemma of game theory
(or the older ‘Tragedy of the Commons’) in which a payoff matrix can be
constructed to show how individually rational actions to maximise
self-interest result in less than maximal outcomes. Consider this matrix,
for example, where the cell numbers stand for years in jail:
In order to escape this consequence, the sovereign
is introduced to change the structure of the payoff matrix so that it does
not seem to profit one to break the law.
Xunzi’s solution, however, does not change the
payoff matrix at all. He simply says that by following the rituals you
will fall into the mutually beneficial behaviour desired. The question
will be however, given that the human desire to pursue profit remains
intact, and human reason operating upon that desire likewise, why would
you follow the ritual when not doing so would be to your advantage?
So much for the first part of the coordination of
interests. In the second place, it is observed that actual social
cooperation (not just limits on competition) is required for Man to
achieve his greatest prosperity.
The products of the hundred crafts are means to nurture a person, but even
the most capable cannot engage in every craft, nor can people each fill
every official post. If they live apart and do not help each other, then
they will be impoverished. If they live together but have no social
divisions, then they will struggle with each other. Poverty is a
catastrophe and struggle is a disaster.
By the introduction of ritual, people are divided
into the appropriate classes who recognise their roles in the greater
society. When they recognise their roles and do not attempt to usurp the
roles of other classes, then they are able to maximise their contributions
to society. Farmers will farm and craftsmen will craft, while the emperor
rules and the scholars administer. The picture that Xunzi gives is of a
fairly rigidly divided society, but we could set that aside and simply
recognise that norms of behaviour beyond mere prudential self-interest are
required in order to make the best use of the various skills of the
people.
2.
The Regulation of Feelings
Another reason that Xunzi gives for the
introduction of ritual is so that our natural emotions may be expressible
harmlessly, or even beneficially. Xunzi recognises that humans have
emotions that they will desire to express, but that the unrestrained or
undisciplined expression may lead to great harms. In the case of sadness
upon the death of a loved one, the expression of emotion and respect are
regulated by the funeral rites, and Xunzi gives a long (very long)
explanation of the merits of the rites being just so and the reasons for
the differentiation in rites between different layers of society.[3] In the case of various joyous
emotions, he explains how the need to express those emotions may be
satisfied in various appropriate forms of music.[4] (In this he disagrees with the
Mohists, who thought that music was pointless and wasteful.)
In every case ritual begins in that which must be released, reaches full
development in giving it proper form, and finishes in providing it
satisfaction. And so when ritual is at its most perfect, the requirements
of inner dispositions and proper form are both completely fulfilled.[5]
By channeling these emotional expressions through
ritual and music one beautifies life as well as imposing upon it good
order.
b.
Its Method
If the nature of humans is bad, and yet we wish
them to be good (and they wish themselves to be good,) then it follows
that their nature must be tamed. This is what ritual does. Xunzi saw the
achievement of goodness in a person as a product of the deliberate
cultivation of correct behaviours and attitudes; morality was definitely
to be attributed to the nurture side of the nature/nurture divide, a
product of culture and cultivation.
In every case, the nature of a thing is the accomplishment of Heaven. It
cannot be learned. It cannot be worked at. Ritual and
yi are what the sage produces. They
are things that people become capable of through learning, things that are
achieved through working at them.[6]
The attitude is to be contrasted with that of
Mencius, for whom ritual was a more or less direct outgrowth from those
seeds of goodness he identified in human nature. For Xunzi, on the other
hand, ritual was a curb on our natural tendencies.
Crooked wood must await steaming and straightening on the shaping frame,
and only then does it become straight. Blunt metal must await honing and
grinding, and only then does it become sharp.
Repeated performance and practice and study of the
rituals will have the effect of altering one’s nature so that the
behaviour mandated by the rituals will become natural to one. In this
respect the appropriate comparison is to Aristotle who developed a virtue
ethics in which the virtues are dispositions to behave in the appropriate
way, and those dispositions are the target of training that attempts to
make the appropriate behaviours matters of habit. For example, when one is
given reason to believe that a certain degree of willingness to face up to
danger is required in order to have the virtue of courage, and one
believes that one is lacking in that disposition, then one determines to
behave as if one had the
appropriate virtue and continue to so act until the behaviour becomes
customary to one or a habit, and then becomes a natural disposition; at
which time one can say that one has the virtue.[7]
c.
Its Origin
Xunzi does not think that the benefits of ritual
are simply those of conventionalised behaviour. These benefits will only
follow if the conventions (rituals) are appropriate to their function and
respect the nature of humans. No doubt these are difficult to discover,
but we are lucky in that the ancient sages provided a number of signposts
(biao 表) to the proper Way.
[8]
Those who cross waters mark out the deep places, but if the markers are
not clear, people will fall in. Those who order the people mark out the
Way, but if the markers are not clear, there will be chaos. The rituals
are those markers.
Given, however, that the sages were as human as
ourselves, the obvious question is how the sages managed to arrive at
their knowledge of the Way. Xunzi says that there is no mystery: they
discovered proper behaviour in the same way that men discovered the other
arts of civilised life – through effort and intelligence.[9]
In every case ritual and
yi are produced from the deliberate effort of the sage; they are not
produced from people’s nature. Thus when the potter mixes up clay and
makes vessels, the vessels are produced from the deliberate efforts of the
craftsmen; they are not produced from human nature.
…
Sages accumulated[10] reflections and thoughts and practiced deliberate efforts and reasoned
activities in order to produce ritual and
yi and in order to establish proper
models and measures.
But in that case, why do we need to follow the Way
of the sages? Is it not possible for us to also apply our intelligence to
discover the Way?
I say, they
can do it, but they cannot be made to do it
However
One’s feet can walk everywhere under Heaven. Even so, there has not yet
been anyone who who has been able to walk everywhere under Heaven. It has
never been that craftsmen, carpenters, farmers, and merchants cannot do
each other’s business, however, none have ever been able to do each
other’s business. Looking at it in this way, then one is not always able
to do what one can do. The problem is, essentially, that people don’t have the time to invent all the arts of civilisation from scratch – and civilisation could not flourish if they were required to do so. We all stand on the shoulders of giants.
[1]
Xz, 19 (‘Discourse on
Ritual’)
[2]
The others being
‘diffidence’ (mistrust) and ‘glory’ (power-seeking) as described
in Leviathan,
xiii.3-9
[3]
Xz, c. 19
[4]
XZ, c. 20 (Discourse
on Music’)
[5]
Xz, c. 19
[6]
Xz, c. 23 (‘Human
Nature is Bad’)
[7]
Nicomachean Ethics
[8]
Xz, 17
[9]
Xz, 23
[10]
I have given the
alternative translation of this passage to that in Potter’s main
text. |